词条 | evolution |
释义 | evolution scientific theory Introduction theory in biology postulating that the various types of plants, animals, and other living things on Earth have their origin in other preexisting types and that the distinguishable differences are due to modifications in successive generations. The theory of evolution is one of the fundamental keystones of modern biological theory. The diversity of the living world is staggering. More than 2 million existing species of organisms have been named and described; many more remain to be discovered—from 10 million to 30 million, according to some estimates. What is impressive is not just the numbers but also the incredible heterogeneity in size, shape, and way of life—from lowly bacteria, measuring less than a thousandth of a millimetre in diameter, to stately sequoias, rising 100 metres (300 feet) above the ground and weighing several thousand tons; from bacteria living in hot springs at temperatures near the boiling point of water to fungi and algae thriving on the ice masses of Antarctica and in saline pools at −23 °C (−9 °F); and from giant tube worms discovered living near hydrothermal vents on the dark ocean floor to spiders and larkspur plants existing on the slopes of Mount Everest more than 6,000 metres (19,700 feet) above sea level. The virtually infinite variations on life are the fruit of the evolutionary process. All living creatures are related by descent from common ancestors. Humans and other mammals descend from shrewlike creatures that lived more than 150 million years ago; mammals, birds, reptiles, amphibians, and fishes share as ancestors aquatic worms that lived 600 million years ago; and all plants and animals derive from bacteria-like microorganisms that originated more than 3 billion years ago. Biological evolution is a process of descent with modification. Lineages of organisms change through generations; diversity arises because the lineages that descend from common ancestors diverge through time. The 19th-century English naturalist Charles Darwin (Darwin, Charles) argued that organisms come about by evolution, and he provided a scientific explanation, essentially correct but incomplete, of how evolution occurs and why it is that organisms have features—such as wings, eyes, and kidneys—clearly structured to serve specific functions. natural selection was the fundamental concept in his explanation. Natural selection occurs because individuals having more-useful traits, such as more-acute vision or swifter legs, survive better and produce more progeny than individuals with less-favourable traits. genetics, a science born in the 20th century, reveals in detail how natural selection works and led to the development of the modern theory of evolution. Beginning in the 1960s, a related scientific discipline, molecular biology, enormously advanced knowledge of biological evolution and made it possible to investigate detailed problems that had seemed completely out of reach only a short time previously—for example, how similar the genes of humans and chimpanzees might be (they differ in about 1–2 percent of the units that make up the genes). This article discusses evolution as it applies generally to living things. For a discussion of human evolution, see the article human evolution. For a more complete treatment of a discipline that has proved essential to the study of evolution, see the articles genetics, human and heredity. Specific aspects of evolution are discussed in the articles coloration and mimicry. Applications of evolutionary theory to plant and animal breeding are discussed in the articles plant breeding and animal breeding. An overview of the evolution of life as a major characteristic of Earth's history is given in community ecology: Evolution of the biosphere (community ecology). A detailed discussion of the life and thought of Charles Darwin is found in the article Darwin, Charles. General overview The evidence for evolution Darwin and other 19th-century biologists found compelling evidence for biological evolution in the comparative study of living organisms, in their geographic distribution, and in the fossil remains of extinct organisms. Since Darwin's time, the evidence from these sources has become considerably stronger and more comprehensive, while biological disciplines that emerged more recently—genetics, biochemistry, physiology, ecology, animal behaviour (ethology), and especially molecular biology—have supplied powerful additional evidence and detailed confirmation. The amount of information about evolutionary history stored in the DNA and proteins of living things is virtually unlimited; scientists can reconstruct any detail of the evolutionary history of life by investing sufficient time and laboratory resources. Evolutionists no longer are concerned with obtaining evidence to support the fact of evolution but rather are concerned with what sorts of knowledge can be obtained from different sources of evidence. The following sections identify the most productive of these sources and illustrate the types of information they have provided. The fossil record Paleontologists (paleontology) have recovered and studied the fossil remains of many thousands of organisms that lived in the past. This fossil record shows that many kinds of extinct organisms were very different in form from any now living. It also shows successions of organisms through time (see faunal succession, law of; geochronology: Determining the relationships of fossils with rock strata (geochronology)), manifesting their transition from one form to another. (See figure-->.) When an organism dies, it is usually destroyed by other forms of life and by weathering processes. On rare occasions some body parts—particularly hard ones such as shells, teeth, or bones—are preserved by being buried in mud or protected in some other way from predators and weather. Eventually, they may become petrified and preserved indefinitely with the rocks in which they are embedded. Methods such as radiometric dating—measuring the amounts of natural radioactive atoms that remain in certain minerals to determine the elapsed time since they were constituted—make it possible to estimate the time period when the rocks, and the fossils associated with them, were formed. Radiometric dating indicates that Earth was formed about 4.5 billion years ago. The earliest fossils resemble microorganisms such as bacteria and cyanobacteria ( blue-green algae); the oldest of these fossils appear in rocks 3.5 billion years old (see Precambrian time). The oldest known animal fossils, about 700 million years old, come from the so-called Ediacara fauna, small wormlike creatures with soft bodies. Numerous fossils belonging to many living phyla and exhibiting mineralized skeletons appear in rocks about 540 million years old. These organisms are different from organisms living now and from those living at intervening times. Some are so radically different that paleontologists have created new phyla in order to classify them. (See Cambrian Period.) The first vertebrates, animals with backbones, appeared about 400 million years ago; the first mammals, less than 200 million years ago. The history of life recorded by fossils presents compelling evidence of evolution. The fossil record is incomplete. Of the small proportion of organisms preserved as fossils, only a tiny fraction have been recovered and studied by paleontologists. In some cases the succession of forms over time has been reconstructed in detail. One example is the evolution of the horse, shown in the figure-->. The horse can be traced to an animal the size of a dog having several toes on each foot and teeth appropriate for browsing; this animal, called the dawn horse (genus Hyracotherium), lived more than 50 million years ago. The most recent form, the modern horse (Equus), is much larger in size, is one-toed, and has teeth appropriate for grazing. The transitional forms are well preserved as fossils, as are many other kinds of extinct horses that evolved in different directions and left no living descendants. Using recovered fossils, paleontologists have reconstructed examples of radical evolutionary transitions in form and function. For example, the lower jaw of reptiles contains several bones, but that of mammals only one. The other bones in the reptile jaw unmistakably evolved into bones now found in the mammalian ear. At first, such a transition would seem unlikely—it is hard to imagine what function such bones could have had during their intermediate stages. Yet paleontologists discovered two transitional forms of mammal-like reptiles, called therapsids, that had a double jaw joint (i.e., two hinge points side by side)—one joint consisting of the bones that persist in the mammalian jaw and the other composed of the quadrate and articular bones, which eventually became the hammer and anvil of the mammalian ear. (See also mammal: Skeleton (mammal).) For skeptical contemporaries of Darwin, the “ missing link”—the absence of any known transitional form between apes and humans—was a battle cry, as it remained for uninformed people afterward. Not one but many creatures intermediate between living apes and humans have since been found as fossils. The oldest known fossil hominin (Hominidae)s—i.e., primates belonging to the human lineage after it separated from lineages going to the apes—are 6 million to 7 million years old, come from Africa, and are known as Sahelanthropus and Orrorin (or Praeanthropus), which were predominantly bipedal when on the ground but which had very small brains. Ardipithecus lived about 4.4 million years ago, also in Africa. Numerous fossil remains from diverse African origins are known of Australopithecus, a hominin that appeared between 3 million and 4 million years ago. Australopithecus had an upright human stance but a cranial capacity of less than 500 cc (equivalent to a brain weight of about 500 grams), comparable to that of a gorilla or a chimpanzee and about one-third that of humans. Its head displayed a mixture of ape and human characteristics—a low forehead and a long, apelike face but with teeth proportioned like those of humans. Other early hominins partly contemporaneous with Australopithecus include Kenyanthropus and Paranthropus; both had comparatively small brains, although some species of Paranthropus had larger bodies. Paranthropus represents a side branch in the hominin lineage that became extinct. Along with increased cranial capacity, other human characteristics have been found in Homo habilis, which lived about 1.5 million to 2 million years ago in Africa and had a cranial capacity of more than 600 cc (brain weight of 600 grams), and in H. erectus (Homo erectus), which lived between 0.5 million and more than 1.5 million years ago, apparently ranged widely over Africa, Asia, and Europe, and had a cranial capacity of 800 to 1,100 cc (brain weight of 800 to 1,100 grams). The brain sizes of H. ergaster, H. antecessor, and H. heidelbergensis were roughly that of the brain of H. erectus, some of which species were partly contemporaneous, though they lived in different regions of the Eastern Hemisphere. (See also human evolution.) Structural similarities The skeletons (skeleton) of turtles, horses, humans, birds, and bats are strikingly similar, in spite of the different ways of life of these animals and the diversity of their environments. The correspondence, bone by bone, can easily be seen not only in the limbs (as shown in the figure-->) but also in every other part of the body. From a purely practical point of view, it is incomprehensible that a turtle should swim, a horse run, a person write, and a bird or a bat fly with forelimb structures built of the same bones. An engineer could design better limbs in each case. But if it is accepted that all of these skeletons inherited their structures from a common ancestor and became modified only as they adapted to different ways of life, the similarity of their structures makes sense. comparative anatomy investigates the homologies (homology), or inherited similarities, among organisms in bone structure and in other parts of the body. The correspondence of structures is typically very close among some organisms—the different varieties of songbirds, for instance—but becomes less so as the organisms being compared are less closely related in their evolutionary history. The similarities are less between mammals and birds than they are among mammals, and they are still less between mammals and fishes. Similarities in structure, therefore, not only manifest evolution but also help to reconstruct the phylogeny, or evolutionary history, of organisms. Comparative anatomy also reveals why most organismic structures are not perfect. Like the forelimbs of turtles, horses, humans, birds, and bats, an organism's body parts are less than perfectly adapted because they are modified from an inherited structure rather than designed from completely “raw” materials for a specific purpose. The imperfection of structures is evidence for evolution and against antievolutionist arguments that invoke intelligent design (see below Intelligent design and its critics (evolution)). Embryonic development and vestiges Darwin and his followers found support for evolution in the study of embryology, the science that investigates the development of organisms from fertilized egg to time of birth or hatching. vertebrates, from fishes through lizards to humans, develop in ways that are remarkably similar during early stages, but they become more and more differentiated as the embryos approach maturity. The similarities persist longer between organisms that are more closely related (e.g., humans and monkeys) than between those less closely related (humans and sharks). Common developmental patterns reflect evolutionary kinship. Lizards and humans share a developmental pattern inherited from their remote common ancestor; the inherited pattern of each was modified only as the separate descendant lineages evolved in different directions. The common embryonic stages of the two creatures reflect the constraints imposed by this common inheritance, which prevents changes that have not been necessitated by their diverging environments and ways of life. The embryos of humans and other nonaquatic vertebrates exhibit gill slits even though they never breathe through gills. These slits are found in the embryos of all vertebrates because they share as common ancestors the fish in which these structures first evolved. Human embryos also exhibit by the fourth week of development a well-defined tail, which reaches maximum length at six weeks. Similar embryonic tails are found in other mammals, such as dogs, horses, and monkeys; in humans, however, the tail eventually shortens, persisting only as a rudiment in the adult coccyx. A close evolutionary relationship between organisms that appear drastically different as adults can sometimes be recognized by their embryonic homologies. barnacles, for example, are sedentary crustaceans with little apparent likeness to such free-swimming crustaceans as lobsters, shrimps, or copepods. Yet barnacles pass through a free-swimming larval stage, the nauplius, which is unmistakably similar to that of other crustacean larvae. Embryonic rudiments that never fully develop, such as the gill slits in humans, are common in all sorts of animals. Some, however, like the tail rudiment in humans, persist as adult vestiges, reflecting evolutionary ancestry. The most familiar rudimentary organ in humans is the vermiform appendix. This wormlike structure attaches to a short section of intestine called the cecum, which is located at the point where the large and small intestines join. The human vermiform appendix is a functionless vestige of a fully developed organ present in other mammals, such as the rabbit and other herbivores, where a large cecum and appendix store vegetable cellulose to enable its digestion with the help of bacteria. Vestiges are instances of imperfections—like the imperfections seen in anatomical structures—that argue against creation by design but are fully understandable as a result of evolution. biogeography Darwin also saw a confirmation of evolution in the geographic distribution of plants and animals, and later knowledge has reinforced his observations. For example, there are about 1,500 known species of Drosophila vinegar flies (vinegar fly) in the world; nearly one-third of them live in Hawaii and nowhere else, although the total area of the archipelago is less than one-twentieth the area of California or Germany. Also in Hawaii are more than 1,000 species of snails and other land mollusks that exist nowhere else. This unusual diversity is easily explained by evolution. The islands of Hawaii are extremely isolated and have had few colonizers—i.e, animals and plants that arrived there from elsewhere and established populations. Those species that did colonize the islands found many unoccupied ecological niches, local environments suited to sustaining them and lacking predators that would prevent them from multiplying. In response, these species rapidly diversified; this process of diversifying in order to fill ecological niches is called adaptive radiation. Each of the world's continents has its own distinctive collection of animals and plants. In Africa are rhinoceroses, hippopotamuses, lions, hyenas, giraffes, zebras, lemurs, monkeys with narrow noses and nonprehensile tails, chimpanzees, and gorillas. South America, which extends over much the same latitudes as Africa, has none of these animals; it instead has pumas, jaguars, tapir, llamas, raccoons, opossums, armadillos, and monkeys with broad noses and large prehensile tails. These vagaries of biogeography are not due solely to the suitability of the different environments. There is no reason to believe that South American animals are not well suited to living in Africa or those of Africa to living in South America. The islands of Hawaii are no better suited than other Pacific islands for vinegar flies, nor are they less hospitable than other parts of the world for many absent organisms. In fact, although no large mammals are native to the Hawaiian islands, pigs and goats have multiplied there as wild animals since being introduced by humans. This absence of many species from a hospitable environment in which an extraordinary variety of other species flourish can be explained by the theory of evolution, which holds that species can exist and evolve only in geographic areas that were colonized by their ancestors. molecular biology The field of molecular biology provides the most detailed and convincing evidence available for biological evolution. In its unveiling of the nature of DNA and the workings of organisms at the level of enzymes and other protein molecules, it has shown that these molecules hold information about an organism's ancestry. This has made it possible to reconstruct evolutionary events that were previously unknown and to confirm and adjust the view of events already known. The precision with which these events can be reconstructed is one reason the evidence from molecular biology is so compelling. Another reason is that molecular evolution has shown all living organisms, from bacteria to humans, to be related by descent from common ancestors. A remarkable uniformity exists in the molecular components of organisms—in the nature of the components as well as in the ways in which they are assembled and used. In all bacteria, plants, animals, and humans, the DNA comprises a different sequence of the same four component nucleotides, and all the various proteins are synthesized from different combinations and sequences of the same 20 amino acids, although several hundred other amino acids do exist. The genetic code by which the information contained in the DNA of the cell nucleus is passed on to proteins (protein) is virtually everywhere the same. Similar metabolic pathways—sequences of biochemical reactions (see metabolism)—are used by the most diverse organisms to produce energy and to make up the cell components. This unity reveals the genetic continuity and common ancestry of all organisms. There is no other rational way to account for their molecular uniformity when numerous alternative structures are equally likely. The genetic code serves as an example. Each particular sequence of three nucleotides in the nuclear DNA acts as a pattern for the production of exactly the same amino acid in all organisms. This is no more necessary than it is for a language to use a particular combination of letters to represent a particular object. If it is found that certain sequences of letters—planet, tree, woman—are used with identical meanings in a number of different books, one can be sure that the languages used in those books are of common origin. genes and proteins are long molecules that contain information in the sequence of their components in much the same way as sentences of the English language contain information in the sequence of their letters and words. The sequences that make up the genes are passed on from parents to offspring and are identical except for occasional changes introduced by mutations. As an illustration, one may assume that two books are being compared. Both books are 200 pages long and contain the same number of chapters. Closer examination reveals that the two books are identical page for page and word for word, except that an occasional word—say, one in 100—is different. The two books cannot have been written independently; either one has been copied from the other, or both have been copied, directly or indirectly, from the same original book. Similarly, if each component nucleotide of DNA is represented by one letter, the complete sequence of nucleotides in the DNA of a higher organism would require several hundred books of hundreds of pages, with several thousand letters on each page. When the “pages” (or sequences of nucleotides) in these “books” (organisms) are examined one by one, the correspondence in the “letters” (nucleotides) gives unmistakable evidence of common origin. The two arguments presented above are based on different grounds, although both attest to evolution. Using the alphabet analogy, the first argument says that languages that use the same dictionary—the same genetic code and the same 20 amino acids—cannot be of independent origin. The second argument, concerning similarity in the sequence of nucleotides in the DNA (and thus the sequence of amino acids in the proteins), says that books with very similar texts cannot be of independent origin. The evidence of evolution revealed by molecular biology goes even farther. The degree of similarity in the sequence of nucleotides or of amino acids can be precisely quantified. For example, in humans and chimpanzees, the protein molecule called cytochrome c, which serves a vital function in respiration within cells (cellular respiration), consists of the same 104 amino acids in exactly the same order. It differs, however, from the cytochrome c of rhesus monkeys by 1 amino acid, from that of horses by 11 additional amino acids, and from that of tuna by 21 additional amino acids. The degree of similarity reflects the recency of common ancestry. Thus, the inferences from comparative anatomy and other disciplines concerning evolutionary history can be tested in molecular studies of DNA and proteins by examining their sequences of nucleotides and amino acids. (See below DNA and protein as informational macromolecules (evolution).) The authority of this kind of test is overwhelming; each of the thousands of genes and thousands of proteins contained in an organism provides an independent test of that organism's evolutionary history. Not all possible tests have been performed, but many hundreds have been done, and not one has given evidence contrary to evolution. There is probably no other notion in any field of science that has been as extensively tested and as thoroughly corroborated as the evolutionary origin of living organisms. History of evolutionary theory Early ideas All human cultures have developed their own explanations for the origin (creation myth) of the world and of human beings and other creatures. Traditional Judaism and Christianity explain the origin of living beings and their adaptations to their environments (environment)—wings, gills, hands, flowers—as the handiwork of an omniscient God. The philosophers of ancient Greece (Greek religion) had their own creation myths. Anaximander proposed that animals could be transformed from one kind into another, and Empedocles speculated that they were made up of various combinations of preexisting parts. Closer to modern evolutionary ideas were the proposals of early Church Fathers (Church Father) such as Gregory of Nazianzus (Gregory of Nazianzus, Saint) and Augustine (Augustine, Saint), both of whom maintained that not all species of plants and animals were created by God; rather, some had developed in historical times from God's creations. Their motivation was not biological but religious—it would have been impossible to hold representatives of all species in a single vessel such as Noah's Ark; hence, some species must have come into existence only after the Flood. The notion that organisms may change by natural processes was not investigated as a biological subject by Christian (Christianity) theologians of the Middle Ages, but it was, usually incidentally, considered as a possibility by many, including Albertus Magnus (Albertus Magnus, Saint) and his student Thomas Aquinas (Aquinas, Thomas, Saint). Aquinas concluded, after detailed discussion, that the development of living creatures such as maggots and flies from nonliving matter such as decaying meat was not incompatible with Christian faith or philosophy. But he left it to others to determine whether this actually happened. The idea of progress, particularly the belief in unbounded human progress, was central to the Enlightenment of the 18th century, particularly in France among such philosophers as the marquis de Condorcet (Condorcet, Marie-Jean-Antoine-Nicolas de Caritat, marquis de) and Denis Diderot (Diderot, Denis) and such scientists as Georges-Louis Leclerc, comte de Buffon (Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc, count de). But belief in progress did not necessarily lead to the development of a theory of evolution. Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (Maupertuis, Pierre-Louis Moreau de) proposed the spontaneous generation and extinction of organisms as part of his theory of origins, but he advanced no theory of evolution—i.e., the transformation of one species into another through knowable, natural causes. Buffon, one of the greatest naturalists of the time, explicitly considered—and rejected—the possible descent of several species from a common ancestor. He postulated that organisms arise from organic molecules by spontaneous generation, so that there could be as many kinds of animals and plants as there are viable combinations of organic molecules. The English physician Erasmus Darwin (Darwin, Erasmus), grandfather of Charles Darwin, offered in his Zoonomia; or, The Laws of Organic Life (1794–96) some evolutionary speculations, but they were not further developed and had no real influence on subsequent theories. The Swedish botanist Carolus Linnaeus (Linnaeus, Carolus) devised the hierarchical system of plant and animal classification that is still in use in a modernized form. Although he insisted on the fixity of species, his classification (taxonomy) system eventually contributed much to the acceptance of the concept of common descent. The great French naturalist Jean-Baptiste de Monet, chevalier de Lamarck (Lamarck, Jean-Baptiste), held the enlightened view of his age that living organisms represent a progression, with humans as the highest form. From this idea he proposed, in the early years of the 19th century, the first broad theory of evolution. Organisms evolve through eons of time from lower to higher forms, a process still going on, always culminating in human beings. As organisms become adapted to their environments through their habits, modifications occur. Use of an organ or structure reinforces it; disuse leads to obliteration. The characteristics acquired by use and disuse, according to this theory, would be inherited. This assumption, later called the inheritance of acquired (acquired character) characteristics (or Lamarckism), was thoroughly disproved in the 20th century. Although his theory did not stand up in the light of later knowledge, Lamarck made important contributions to the gradual acceptance of biological evolution and stimulated countless later studies. Charles Darwin (Darwin, Charles) The founder of the modern theory of evolution was Charles Darwin (Darwin, Charles). The son and grandson of physicians, he enrolled as a medical student at the University of Edinburgh. After two years, however, he left to study at the University of Cambridge and prepare to become a clergyman. He was not an exceptional student, but he was deeply interested in natural history. On December 27, 1831, a few months after his graduation from Cambridge, he sailed as a naturalist aboard the HMS Beagle on a round-the-world trip that lasted until October 1836. Darwin was often able to disembark for extended trips ashore to collect natural specimens. The discovery of fossil bones from large extinct mammals in Argentina and the observation of numerous species of finches (Galapagos finch) in the Galapagos Islands were among the events credited with stimulating Darwin's interest in how species originate. In 1859 he published On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, a treatise establishing the theory of evolution and, most important, the role of natural selection in determining its course. He published many other books as well, notably The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex (1871), which extends the theory of natural selection to human evolution. Darwin must be seen as a great intellectual revolutionary who inaugurated a new era in the cultural history of humankind, an era that was the second and final stage of the Copernican revolution that had begun in the 16th and 17th centuries under the leadership of men such as Nicolaus Copernicus (Copernicus, Nicolaus), Galileo, and Isaac Newton (Newton, Sir Isaac). The Copernican revolution marked the beginnings of modern science (science, history of). Discoveries in astronomy and physics overturned traditional conceptions of the universe. Earth no longer was seen as the centre of the universe but was seen as a small planet revolving around one of myriad stars; the seasons and the rains that make crops grow, as well as destructive storms and other vagaries of weather, became understood as aspects of natural processes; the revolutions of the planets were now explained by simple laws that also accounted for the motion of projectiles on Earth. The significance of these and other discoveries was that they led to a conception of the universe as a system of matter in motion governed by laws of nature. The workings of the universe no longer needed to be attributed to the ineffable will of a divine Creator; rather, they were brought into the realm of science—an explanation of phenomena through natural laws. Physical phenomena such as tides, eclipses, and positions of the planets could now be predicted whenever the causes were adequately known. Darwin accumulated evidence showing that evolution had occurred, that diverse organisms share common ancestors, and that living beings have changed drastically over the course of Earth's history. More important, however, he extended to the living world the idea of nature as a system of matter in motion governed by natural laws. Before Darwin, the origin of Earth's living things, with their marvelous contrivances for adaptation, had been attributed to the design (intelligent design) of an omniscient God. He had created the fish in the waters, the birds in the air, and all sorts of animals and plants on the land. God had endowed these creatures with gills for breathing, wings for flying, and eyes for seeing, and he had coloured birds and flowers so that human beings could enjoy them and recognize God's wisdom. Christian theologians, from Aquinas on, had argued that the presence of design, so evident in living beings, demonstrates the existence of a supreme Creator; the argument from design was Aquinas's “fifth way” for proving the existence of God. In 19th-century England the eight Bridgewater Treatises were commissioned so that eminent scientists and philosophers would expand on the marvels of the natural world and thereby set forth “the Power, wisdom, and goodness of God as manifested in the Creation.” The British theologian William Paley (Paley, William) in his Natural Theology (1802) used natural history, physiology, and other contemporary knowledge to elaborate the argument from design. If a person should find a watch, even in an uninhabited desert, Paley contended, the harmony of its many parts would force him to conclude that it had been created by a skilled watchmaker; and, Paley went on, how much more intricate and perfect in design is the human eye, with its transparent lens, its retina placed at the precise distance for forming a distinct image, and its large nerve transmitting signals to the brain. The argument from design seems to be forceful. A ladder is made for climbing, a knife for cutting, and a watch for telling time; their functional design leads to the conclusion that they have been fashioned by a carpenter, a smith, or a watchmaker. Similarly, the obvious functional design of animals and plants seems to denote the work of a Creator. It was Darwin's genius that he provided a natural explanation for the organization and functional design of living beings. (For additional discussion of the argument from design and its revival in the 1990s, see below Intelligent design and its critics (evolution).) Darwin accepted the facts of adaptation—hands are for grasping, eyes for seeing, lungs for breathing. But he showed that the multiplicity of plants and animals, with their exquisite and varied adaptations, could be explained by a process of natural selection, without recourse to a Creator or any designer agent. This achievement would prove to have intellectual and cultural implications more profound and lasting than his multipronged evidence that convinced contemporaries of the fact of evolution. Darwin's theory of natural selection is summarized in the Origin of Species as follows: As many more individuals are produced than can possibly survive, there must in every case be a struggle for existence, either one individual with another of the same species, or with the individuals of distinct species, or with the physical conditions of life.…Can it, then, be thought improbable, seeing that variations useful to man have undoubtedly occurred, that other variations useful in some way to each being in the great and complex battle of life, should sometimes occur in the course of thousands of generations? If such do occur, can we doubt (remembering that many more individuals are born than can possibly survive) that individuals having any advantage, however slight, over others, would have the best chance of surviving and of procreating their kind? On the other hand, we may feel sure that any variation in the least degree injurious would be rigidly destroyed. This preservation of favourable variations and the rejection of injurious variations, I call Natural Selection. Natural selection was proposed by Darwin primarily to account for the adaptive organization of living beings; it is a process that promotes or maintains adaptation. Evolutionary change through time and evolutionary diversification (multiplication of species) are not directly promoted by natural selection, but they often ensue as by-products of natural selection as it fosters adaptation to different environments. Modern conceptions The Darwinian aftermath The publication of the Origin of Species produced considerable public excitement. Scientists, politicians, clergymen, and notables of all kinds read and discussed the book, defending or deriding Darwin's ideas. The most visible actor in the controversies immediately following publication was the English biologist T.H. Huxley (Huxley, T.H.), known as “Darwin's bulldog,” who defended the theory of evolution with articulate and sometimes mordant words on public occasions as well as in numerous writings. Evolution by natural selection was indeed a favourite topic in society salons during the 1860s and beyond. But serious scientific controversies also arose, first in Britain and then on the Continent and in the United States. One occasional participant in the discussion was the British naturalist Alfred Russel Wallace (Wallace, Alfred Russel), who had hit upon the idea of natural selection independently and had sent a short manuscript about it to Darwin from the Malay Archipelago, where he was collecting specimens and writing. On July 1, 1858, one year before the publication of the Origin, a paper jointly authored by Wallace and Darwin was presented, in the absence of both, to the Linnean Society in London—with apparently little notice. Greater credit is duly given to Darwin than to Wallace for the idea of evolution by natural selection; Darwin developed the theory in considerably more detail, provided far more evidence for it, and was primarily responsible for its acceptance. Wallace's views differed from Darwin's in several ways, most importantly in that Wallace did not think natural selection sufficient to account for the origin of human beings, which in his view required direct divine intervention. A younger English contemporary of Darwin, with considerable influence during the latter part of the 19th and in the early 20th century, was Herbert Spencer (Spencer, Herbert). A philosopher rather than a biologist, he became an energetic proponent of evolutionary ideas, popularized a number of slogans, such as “survival of the fittest” (which was taken up by Darwin in later editions of the Origin), and engaged in social and metaphysical speculations. His ideas considerably damaged proper understanding and acceptance of the theory of evolution by natural selection. Darwin wrote of Spencer's speculations: His deductive manner of treating any subject is wholly opposed to my frame of mind.…His fundamental generalizations (which have been compared in importance by some persons with Newton's laws!) which I dare say may be very valuable under a philosophical point of view, are of such a nature that they do not seem to me to be of any strictly scientific use. Most pernicious was the crude extension by Spencer and others of the notion of the “struggle for existence” to human economic and social life that became known as social Darwinism (see below Scientific acceptance and extension to other disciplines (evolution)). The most serious difficulty facing Darwin's evolutionary theory was the lack of an adequate theory of inheritance that would account for the preservation through the generations of the variations on which natural selection was supposed to act. Contemporary theories of “blending inheritance” proposed that offspring merely struck an average between the characteristics of their parents. But as Darwin became aware, blending inheritance (including his own theory of “pangenesis,” in which each organ and tissue of an organism throws off tiny contributions of itself that are collected in the sex organs and determine the configuration of the offspring) could not account for the conservation of variations, because differences between variant offspring would be halved each generation, rapidly reducing the original variation to the average of the preexisting characteristics. The missing link in Darwin's argument was provided by Mendelian genetics. (Mendelism) About the time the Origin of Species was published, the Augustinian monk Gregor Mendel (Mendel, Gregor) was starting a long series of experiments with peas in the garden of his monastery in Brünn, Austria-Hungary (now Brno, Czech Republic). These experiments and the analysis of their results are by any standard an example of masterly scientific method. Mendel's paper, published in 1866 in the Proceedings of the Natural Science Society of Brünn, formulated the fundamental principles of the theory of heredity that is still current. His theory accounts for biological inheritance through particulate factors (now known as genes) inherited one from each parent, which do not mix or blend but segregate in the formation of the sex cells, or gametes (gamete). Mendel's discoveries remained unknown to Darwin, however, and, indeed, they did not become generally known until 1900, when they were simultaneously rediscovered by a number of scientists on the Continent. In the meantime, Darwinism in the latter part of the 19th century faced an alternative evolutionary theory known as neo-Lamarckism. This hypothesis shared with Lamarck's the importance of use and disuse in the development and obliteration of organs, and it added the notion that the environment acts directly on organic structures, which explained their adaptation to the way of life and environment of the organism. Adherents of this theory discarded natural selection as an explanation for adaptation to the environment. Prominent among the defenders of natural selection was the German biologist August Weismann (Weismann, August (Friedrich Leopold)), who in the 1880s published his germ plasm theory (germ-plasm theory). He distinguished two substances that make up an organism: the soma, which comprises most body parts and organs, and the germ plasm, which contains the cells that give rise to the gametes and hence to progeny. Early in the development of an egg, the germ plasm becomes segregated from the somatic cells that give rise to the rest of the body. This notion of a radical separation between germ plasm and soma—that is, between the reproductive tissues and all other body tissues—prompted Weismann to assert that inheritance of acquired characteristics was impossible, and it opened the way for his championship of natural selection as the only major process that would account for biological evolution. Weismann's ideas became known after 1896 as neo-Darwinism. The synthetic theory The rediscovery in 1900 of Mendel's theory of heredity, by the Dutch botanist and geneticist Hugo de Vries (Vries, Hugo de) and others, led to an emphasis on the role of heredity in evolution. De Vries proposed a new theory of evolution known as mutationism, which essentially did away with natural selection as a major evolutionary process. According to de Vries (who was joined by other geneticists such as William Bateson (Bateson, William) in England), two kinds of variation take place in organisms. One is the “ordinary” variability observed among individuals of a species, which is of no lasting consequence in evolution because, according to de Vries, it could not “lead to a transgression of the species border 【i.e., to establishment of new species】 even under conditions of the most stringent and continued selection.” The other consists of the changes brought about by mutations (mutation), spontaneous alterations of genes that result in large modifications of the organism and give rise to new species: “The new species thus originates suddenly, it is produced by the existing one without any visible preparation and without transition.” Mutationism was opposed by many naturalists and in particular by the so-called biometricians, led by the English statistician Karl Pearson (Pearson, Karl), who defended Darwinian natural selection as the major cause of evolution through the cumulative effects of small, continuous, individual variations (which the biometricians assumed passed from one generation to the next without being limited by Mendel's laws of inheritance 【see Mendelism】). The controversy between mutationists (also referred to at the time as Mendelians) and biometricians approached a resolution in the 1920s and '30s through the theoretical work of geneticists. These scientists used mathematical arguments to show, first, that continuous variation (in such characteristics as body size, number of eggs laid, and the like) could be explained by Mendel's laws and, second, that natural selection acting cumulatively on small variations could yield major evolutionary changes in form and function. Distinguished members of this group of theoretical geneticists were R.A. Fisher (Fisher, Sir Ronald Aylmer) and J.B.S. Haldane (Haldane, J.B.S.) in Britain and Sewall Wright (Wright, Sewall) in the United States. Their work contributed to the downfall of mutationism and, most important, provided a theoretical framework for the integration of genetics into Darwin's theory of natural selection. Yet their work had a limited impact on contemporary biologists for several reasons—it was formulated in a mathematical language that most biologists could not understand; it was almost exclusively theoretical, with little empirical corroboration; and it was limited in scope, largely omitting many issues, such as speciation (the process by which new species are formed), that were of great importance to evolutionists. A major breakthrough came in 1937 with the publication of Genetics and the Origin of Species by Theodosius Dobzhansky (Dobzhansky, Theodosius), a Russian-born American naturalist and experimental geneticist. Dobzhansky's book advanced a reasonably comprehensive account of the evolutionary process in genetic terms, laced with experimental evidence supporting the theoretical argument. Genetics and the Origin of Species may be considered the most important landmark in the formulation of what came to be known as the synthetic theory of evolution, effectively combining Darwinian natural selection and Mendelian genetics. It had an enormous impact on naturalists and experimental biologists, who rapidly embraced the new understanding of the evolutionary process as one of genetic change in populations. Interest in evolutionary studies was greatly stimulated, and contributions to the theory soon began to follow, extending the synthesis of genetics and natural selection to a variety of biological fields. The main writers who, together with Dobzhansky, may be considered the architects of the synthetic theory were the German-born American zoologist Ernst Mayr (Mayr, Ernst), the English zoologist Julian Huxley (Huxley, Sir Julian), the American paleontologist George Gaylord Simpson (Simpson, George Gaylord), and the American botanist George Ledyard Stebbins (Stebbins, George Ledyard, Jr.). These researchers contributed to a burst of evolutionary studies in the traditional biological disciplines and in some emerging ones—notably population genetics and, later, evolutionary ecology (see community ecology). By 1950 acceptance of Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection was universal among biologists, and the synthetic theory had become widely adopted. Molecular biology and Earth sciences The most important line of investigation after 1950 was the application of molecular biology to evolutionary studies. In 1953 the American geneticist James Watson (Watson, James Dewey) and the British biophysicist Francis Crick (Crick, Francis Harry Compton) deduced the molecular structure of DNA (deoxyribonucleic acid), the hereditary material contained in the chromosomes (chromosome) of every cell's nucleus. The genetic information is encoded within the sequence of nucleotides that make up the chainlike DNA molecules. This information determines the sequence of amino acid building blocks of protein molecules, which include, among others, structural proteins such as collagen, respiratory proteins such as hemoglobin, and numerous enzymes responsible for the organism's fundamental life processes. Genetic information contained in the DNA can thus be investigated by examining the sequences of amino acids in the proteins. In the mid-1960s laboratory techniques such as electrophoresis and selective assay of enzymes became available for the rapid and inexpensive study of differences among enzymes and other proteins. The application of these techniques to evolutionary problems made possible the pursuit of issues that earlier could not be investigated—for example, exploring the extent of genetic variation in natural populations (which sets bounds on their evolutionary potential) and determining the amount of genetic change that occurs during the formation of new species. Comparisons of the amino acid sequences of corresponding proteins in different species provided quantitatively precise measures of the divergence among species evolved from common ancestors, a considerable improvement over the typically qualitative evaluations obtained by comparative anatomy and other evolutionary subdisciplines. In 1968 the Japanese geneticist Motoo Kimura proposed the neutrality theory of molecular evolution, which assumes that, at the level of the sequences of nucleotides in DNA and of amino acids in proteins, many changes are adaptively neutral; they have little or no effect on the molecule's function and thus on an organism's fitness within its environment. If the neutrality theory is correct, there should be a “molecular clock” of evolution; that is, the degree to which amino acid or nucleotide sequences diverge between species should provide a reliable estimate of the time since the species diverged. This would make it possible to reconstruct an evolutionary history that would reveal the order of branching of different lineages, such as those leading to humans, chimpanzees, and orangutans, as well as the time in the past when the lineages split from one another. During the 1970s and '80s it gradually became clear that the molecular clock is not exact; nevertheless, into the early 21st century it continued to provide the most reliable evidence for reconstructing evolutionary history. (See below The molecular clock of evolution (evolution) and The neutrality theory of molecular evolution (evolution).) The laboratory techniques of DNA cloning and sequencing have provided a new and powerful means of investigating evolution at the molecular level. The fruits of this technology began to accumulate during the 1980s following the development of automated DNA-sequencing machines and the invention of the polymerase chain reaction (PCR), a simple and inexpensive technique that obtains, in a few hours, billions or trillions of copies of a specific DNA sequence or gene. Major research efforts such as the Human Genome Project further improved the technology for obtaining long DNA sequences rapidly and inexpensively. By the first few years of the 21st century, the full DNA sequence—i.e., the full genetic complement, or genome—had been obtained for more than 20 higher organisms, including human beings, the house mouse (Mus musculus), the rat Rattus norvegicus, the vinegar fly Drosophila melanogaster, the mosquito Anopheles gambiae, the nematode worm Caenorhabditis elegans, the malaria parasite Plasmodium falciparum, the mustard weed Arabidopsis thaliana, and the yeast Saccharomyces cerevisiae, as well as for numerous microorganisms. The Earth sciences also experienced, in the second half of the 20th century, a conceptual revolution with considerable consequence to the study of evolution. The theory of plate tectonics, which was formulated in the late 1960s, revealed that the configuration and position of the continents and oceans are dynamic, rather than static, features of Earth. Oceans grow and shrink, while continents break into fragments or coalesce into larger masses. The continents move across Earth's surface at rates of a few centimetres a year, and over millions of years of geologic history this movement profoundly alters the face of the planet, causing major climatic changes along the way. These previously unsuspected massive modifications of Earth's past environments are, of necessity, reflected in the evolutionary history of life. biogeography, the evolutionary study of plant and animal distribution, has been revolutionized by the knowledge, for example, that Africa and South America were part of a single landmass some 200 million years ago and that the Indian subcontinent was not connected with Asia until geologically recent times. ecology, the study of the interactions of organisms with their environments, has evolved from descriptive studies—“natural history”—into a vigorous biological discipline with a strong mathematical component, both in the development of theoretical models and in the collection and analysis of quantitative data. Evolutionary ecology (see community ecology) is an active field of evolutionary biology; another is evolutionary ethology, the study of the evolution of animal behaviour. sociobiology, the evolutionary study of social behaviour, is perhaps the most active subfield of ethology. It is also the most controversial, because of its extension to human societies. The cultural impact of evolutionary theory Scientific acceptance and extension to other disciplines The theory of evolution makes statements about three different, though related, issues: (1) the fact of evolution—that is, that organisms are related by common descent; (2) evolutionary history—the details of when lineages split from one another and of the changes that occurred in each lineage; and (3) the mechanisms or processes by which evolutionary change occurs. The first issue is the most fundamental and the one established with utmost certainty. Darwin gathered much evidence in its support, but evidence has accumulated continuously ever since, derived from all biological disciplines. The evolutionary origin of organisms is today a scientific conclusion established with the kind of certainty attributable to such scientific concepts as the roundness of Earth, the motions of the planets, and the molecular composition of matter. This degree of certainty beyond reasonable doubt is what is implied when biologists say that evolution is a “fact”; the evolutionary origin of organisms is accepted by virtually every biologist. But the theory of evolution goes far beyond the general affirmation that organisms evolve. The second and third issues—seeking to ascertain evolutionary relationships between particular organisms and the events of evolutionary history, as well as to explain how and why evolution takes place—are matters of active scientific investigation. Some conclusions are well established. One, for example, is that the chimpanzee and the gorilla are more closely related to humans than is any of those three species to the baboon or other monkeys. Another conclusion is that natural selection, the process postulated by Darwin, explains the configuration of such adaptive features as the human eye and the wings of birds. Many matters are less certain, others are conjectural, and still others—such as the characteristics of the first living things and when they came about—remain completely unknown. Since Darwin, the theory of evolution has gradually extended its influence to other biological disciplines, from physiology to ecology and from biochemistry to systematics. All biological knowledge now includes the phenomenon of evolution. In the words of Theodosius Dobzhansky, “Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution.” The term evolution and the general concept of change through time also have penetrated into scientific language well beyond biology and even into common language. Astrophysicists speak of the evolution of the solar system or of the universe; geologists, of the evolution of Earth's interior; psychologists, of the evolution of the mind; anthropologists, of the evolution of cultures; art historians, of the evolution of architectural styles; and couturiers, of the evolution of fashion. These and other disciplines use the word with only the slightest commonality of meaning—the notion of gradual, and perhaps directional, change over the course of time. Toward the end of the 20th century, specific concepts and processes borrowed from biological evolution and living systems were incorporated into computational research, beginning with the work of the American mathematician John Holland (Holland, John Henry) and others. One outcome of this endeavour was the development of methods for automatically generating computer-based systems that are proficient at given tasks. These systems have a wide variety of potential uses, such as solving practical computational problems, providing machines with the ability to learn from experience, and modeling processes in fields as diverse as ecology, immunology, economics, and even biological evolution itself. To generate computer programs that represent proficient solutions to a problem under study, the computer scientist creates a set of step-by-step procedures, called a genetic algorithm or, more broadly, an evolutionary algorithm, that incorporates analogies of genetic processes—for instance, heredity, mutation, and recombination—as well as of evolutionary processes such as natural selection in the presence of specified environments. The algorithm is designed typically to simulate the biological evolution of a population of individual computer programs through successive generations to improve their “fitness” for carrying out a designated task. Each program in an initial population receives a fitness score that measures how well it performs in a specific “environment”—for example, how efficiently it sorts a list of numbers or allocates the floor space in a new factory design. Only those with the highest scores are selected to “reproduce,” to contribute “hereditary” material—i.e., computer code—to the following generation of programs. The rules of reproduction may involve such elements as recombination (strings of code from the best programs are shuffled and combined into the programs of the next generation) and mutation (bits of code in a few of the new programs are changed at random). The evolutionary algorithm then evaluates each program in the new generation for fitness, winnows out the poorer performers, and allows reproduction to take place once again, with the cycle repeating itself as often as desired. Evolutionary algorithms are simplistic compared with biological evolution, but they have provided robust and powerful mechanisms for finding solutions to all sorts of problems in economics, industrial production, and the distribution of goods and services. (See also artificial intelligence: Evolutionary computing (artificial intelligence).) Darwin's notion of natural selection also has been extended to areas of human discourse outside the scientific setting, particularly in the fields of sociopolitical theory and economics. The extension can be only metaphoric, because in Darwin's intended meaning natural selection applies only to hereditary variations in entities endowed with biological reproduction—that is, to living organisms. That natural selection is a natural process in the living world has been taken by some as a justification for ruthless competition and for “survival of the fittest” in the struggle for economic advantage or for political hegemony. social Darwinism was an influential social philosophy in some circles through the late 19th and early 20th centuries, when it was used as a rationalization for racism, colonialism, and social stratification. At the other end of the political spectrum, Marxist (Marxism) theorists have resorted to evolution by natural selection as an explanation for humankind's political history. Darwinism understood as a process that favours the strong and successful and eliminates the weak and failing has been used to justify alternative and, in some respects, quite diametric economic theories (see economics). These theories share in common the premise that the valuation of all market products depends on a Darwinian process. Specific market commodities are evaluated in terms of the degree to which they conform to specific valuations emanating from the consumers. On the one hand, some of these economic theories are consistent with theories of evolutionary psychology that see preferences as determined largely genetically; as such, they hold that the reactions of markets can be predicted in terms of largely fixed human attributes. The dominant neo-Keynesian (see economics: Keynesian economics (economics)) and monetarist (monetarism) schools of economics make predictions of the macroscopic behaviour of economies (see macroeconomics) based the interrelationship of a few variables; money supply, rate of inflation, and rate of unemployment jointly determine the rate of economic growth. On the other hand, some minority economists, such as the 20th-century Austrian-born British theorist F.A. Hayek (Hayek, F.A.) and his followers, predicate the Darwinian process on individual preferences that are mostly underdetermined and change in erratic or unpredictable ways. According to them, old ways of producing goods and services are continuously replaced by new inventions and behaviours. These theorists affirm that what drives the economy is the ingenuity of individuals and corporations and their ability to bring new and better products to the market. Religious criticism and acceptance The theory of evolution has been seen by some people as incompatible with religious beliefs, particularly those of Christianity. The first chapters of the biblical book of Genesis describe God's creation of the world, the plants, the animals, and human beings. A literal interpretation of Genesis seems incompatible with the gradual evolution of humans and other organisms by natural processes. Independently of the biblical (Bible) narrative, the Christian beliefs in the immortality of the soul and in humans as “created in the image of God” have appeared to many as contrary to the evolutionary origin of humans from nonhuman animals. Religiously motivated attacks started during Darwin's lifetime. In 1874 Charles Hodge (Hodge, Charles), an American Protestant theologian, published What Is Darwinism?, one of the most articulate assaults on evolutionary theory. Hodge perceived Darwin's theory as “the most thoroughly naturalistic that can be imagined and far more atheistic than that of his predecessor Lamarck.” He argued that the design of the human eye evinces that “it has been planned by the Creator, like the design of a watch evinces a watchmaker.” He concluded that “the denial of design in nature is actually the denial of God.” Other Protestant (Protestantism) theologians saw a solution to the difficulty through the argument that God operates through intermediate causes. The origin and motion of the planets could be explained by the law of gravity and other natural processes without denying God's creation and providence. Similarly, evolution could be seen as the natural process through which God brought living beings into existence and developed them according to his plan. Thus, A.H. Strong, the president of Rochester Theological Seminary in New York state, wrote in his Systematic Theology (1885): “We grant the principle of evolution, but we regard it as only the method of divine intelligence.” The brutish ancestry of human beings was not incompatible with their excelling status as creatures in the image of God. Strong drew an analogy with Christ's miraculous conversion of water into wine: “The wine in the miracle was not water because water had been used in the making of it, nor is man a brute because the brute has made some contributions to its creation.” Arguments for and against Darwin (Darwin, Charles)'s theory came from Roman Catholic (Roman Catholicism) theologians as well. Gradually, well into the 20th century, evolution by natural selection came to be accepted by the majority of Christian writers. Pope Pius XII in his encyclical Humani generis (1950; “Of the Human Race”) acknowledged that biological evolution was compatible with the Christian faith, although he argued that God's intervention was necessary for the creation of the human soul. Pope John Paul II, in an address to the Pontifical Academy of Sciences on October 22, 1996, deplored interpreting the Bible's texts as scientific statements rather than religious teachings, adding: New scientific knowledge has led us to realize that the theory of evolution is no longer a mere hypothesis. It is indeed remarkable that this theory has been progressively accepted by researchers, following a series of discoveries in various fields of knowledge. The convergence, neither sought nor fabricated, of the results of work that was conducted independently is in itself a significant argument in favor of this theory. Similar views were expressed by other mainstream Christian denominations. The General Assembly of the United Presbyterian Church in 1982 adopted a resolution stating that “Biblical scholars and theological schools…find that the scientific theory of evolution does not conflict with their interpretation of the origins of life found in Biblical literature.” The Lutheran World Federation in 1965 affirmed that “evolution's assumptions are as much around us as the air we breathe and no more escapable. At the same time theology's affirmations are being made as responsibly as ever. In this sense both science and religion are here to stay, and…need to remain in a healthful tension of respect toward one another.” Similar statements have been advanced by Jewish (Judaism) authorities and those of other major religions. In 1984 the 95th Annual Convention of the Central Conference of American Rabbis adopted a resolution stating: “Whereas the principles and concepts of biological evolution are basic to understanding science…we call upon science teachers and local school authorities in all states to demand quality textbooks that are based on modern, scientific knowledge and that exclude ‘scientific' creationism.” Opposing these views were Christian denominations that continued to hold a literal interpretation of the Bible. A succinct expression of this interpretation is found in the Statement of Belief of the Creation Research Society, founded in 1963 as a “professional organization of trained scientists and interested laypersons who are firmly committed to scientific special creation” (see creationism): The Bible is the Written Word of God, and because it is inspired throughout, all of its assertions are historically and scientifically true in the original autographs. To the student of nature this means that the account of origins in Genesis is a factual presentation of simple historical truths. Many Bible scholars and theologians have long rejected a literal interpretation as untenable, however, because the Bible contains incompatible statements. The very beginning of the book of Genesis presents two different creation narratives. Extending through chapter 1 and the first verses of chapter 2 is the familiar six-day narrative, in which God creates human beings—both “male and female”—in his own image on the sixth day, after creating light, Earth, firmament, fish, fowl, and cattle. But in verse 4 of chapter 2 a different narrative starts, in which God creates a male human, then plants a garden and creates the animals, and only then proceeds to take a rib from the man to make a woman. Biblical scholars point out that the Bible is inerrant with respect to religious truth, not in matters that are of no significance to salvation. Augustine (Augustine, Saint), considered by many the greatest Christian theologian, wrote in the early 5th century in his De Genesi ad litteram (Literal Commentary on Genesis): It is also frequently asked what our belief must be about the form and shape of heaven, according to Sacred Scripture. Many scholars engage in lengthy discussions on these matters, but the sacred writers with their deeper wisdom have omitted them. Such subjects are of no profit for those who seek beatitude. And what is worse, they take up very precious time that ought to be given to what is spiritually beneficial. What concern is it of mine whether heaven is like a sphere and Earth is enclosed by it and suspended in the middle of the universe, or whether heaven is like a disk and the Earth is above it and hovering to one side. Augustine adds later in the same chapter: “In the matter of the shape of heaven, the sacred writers did not wish to teach men facts that could be of no avail for their salvation.” Augustine is saying that the book of Genesis is not an elementary book of astronomy. It is a book about religion, and it is not the purpose of its religious authors to settle questions about the shape of the universe that are of no relevance whatsoever to how to seek salvation. In the same vein, John Paul II said in 1981: The Bible itself speaks to us of the origin of the universe and its make-up, not in order to provide us with a scientific treatise but in order to state the correct relationships of man with God and with the universe. Sacred scripture wishes simply to declare that the world was created by God, and in order to teach this truth it expresses itself in the terms of the cosmology in use at the time of the writer.Any other teaching about the origin and make-up of the universe is alien to the intentions of the Bible, which does not wish to teach how the heavens were made but how one goes to heaven. John Paul's argument was clearly a response to Christian fundamentalists (fundamentalism, Christian) who see in Genesis a literal description of how the world was created by God. In modern times biblical fundamentalists have made up a minority of Christians, but they have periodically gained considerable public and political influence, particularly in the United States. Opposition to the teaching of evolution in the United States can largely be traced to two movements with 19th-century roots, Seventh-day Adventism (Seventh-day Adventist) (see Adventist) and Pentecostalism. Consistent with their emphasis on the seventh-day Sabbath as a memorial of the biblical Creation, Seventh-day Adventists have insisted on the recent creation of life and the universality of the Flood, which they believe deposited the fossil-bearing rocks. This distinctively Adventist interpretation of Genesis became the hard core of “creation science” in the late 20th century and was incorporated into the “balanced-treatment” laws of Arkansas and Louisiana (discussed below). Many Pentecostals, who generally endorse a literal interpretation of the Bible, also have adopted and endorsed the tenets of creation science, including the recent origin of Earth and a geology interpreted in terms of the Flood. They have differed from Seventh-day Adventists and other adherents of creation science, however, in their tolerance of diverse views and the limited import they attribute to the evolution-creation controversy. During the 1920s, biblical fundamentalists helped influence more than 20 state legislatures to debate antievolution laws, and four states—Arkansas, Mississippi, Oklahoma, and Tennessee—prohibited the teaching of evolution in their public schools. A spokesman for the antievolutionists was William Jennings Bryan (Bryan, William Jennings), three times the unsuccessful Democratic candidate for the U.S. presidency, who said in 1922, “We will drive Darwinism from our schools.” In 1925 Bryan took part in the prosecution (see Scopes Trial) of John T. Scopes, a high-school teacher in Dayton, Tennessee, who had admittedly violated the state's law forbidding the teaching of evolution. In 1968 the Supreme Court of the United States declared unconstitutional any law banning the teaching of evolution in public schools. After that time Christian fundamentalists introduced bills in a number of state legislatures ordering that the teaching of “evolution science” be balanced by allocating equal time to creation science (creationism). Creation science maintains that all kinds of organisms abruptly came into existence when God created the universe, that the world is only a few thousand years old, and that the biblical Flood was an actual event that only one pair of each animal species survived. In the 1980s Arkansas and Louisiana passed acts requiring the balanced treatment of evolution science and creation science in their schools, but opponents successfully challenged the acts as violations of the constitutionally mandated separation of church and state. The Arkansas statute was declared unconstitutional in federal court after a public trial in Little Rock. The Louisiana law was appealed all the way to the Supreme Court of the United States, which ruled Louisiana's “Creationism Act” unconstitutional because, by advancing the religious belief that a supernatural being created humankind, which is embraced by the phrase creation science, the act impermissibly endorses religion. intelligent design and its critics William Paley (Paley, William)'s Natural Theology, the book by which he has become best known to posterity, is a sustained argument explaining the obvious design of humans and their parts, as well as the design of all sorts of organisms, in themselves and in their relations to one another and to their environment. Paley's keystone claim is that “there cannot be design without a designer; contrivance, without a contriver; order, without choice;…means suitable to an end, and executing their office in accomplishing that end, without the end ever having been contemplated.” His book has chapters dedicated to the complex design of the human eye; to the human frame, which, he argues, displays a precise mechanical arrangement of bones, cartilage, and joints; to the circulation of the blood and the disposition of blood vessels; to the comparative anatomy of humans and animals; to the digestive system, kidneys, urethra, and bladder; to the wings of birds and the fins of fish; and much more. For more than 300 pages, Paley conveys extensive and accurate biological knowledge in such detail and precision as was available in 1802, the year of the book's publication. After his meticulous description of each biological object or process, Paley draws again and again the same conclusion—only an omniscient and omnipotent deity could account for these marvels and for the enormous diversity of inventions that they entail. On the example of the human eye he wrote: I know no better method of introducing so large a subject, than that of comparing…an eye, for example, with a telescope. As far as the examination of the instrument goes, there is precisely the same proof that the eye was made for vision, as there is that the telescope was made for assisting it. They are made upon the same principles; both being adjusted to the laws by which the transmission and refraction of rays of light are regulated.…For instance, these laws require, in order to produce the same effect, that the rays of light, in passing from water into the eye, should be refracted by a more convex surface than when it passes out of air into the eye. Accordingly we find that the eye of a fish, in that part of it called the crystalline lens, is much rounder than the eye of terrestrial animals. What plainer manifestation of design can there be than this difference? What could a mathematical instrument maker have done more to show his knowledge of 【t】his principle, his application of that knowledge, his suiting of his means to his end…to testify counsel, choice, consideration, purpose? It would be absurd to suppose, he argued, that by mere chance the eye should have consisted, first, of a series of transparent lenses—very different, by the by, even in their substance, from the opaque materials of which the rest of the body is, in general at least, composed, and with which the whole of its surface, this single portion of it excepted, is covered: secondly, of a black cloth or canvas—the only membrane in the body which is black—spread out behind these lenses, so as to receive the image formed by pencils of light transmitted through them; and placed at the precise geometrical distance at which, and at which alone, a distinct image could be formed, namely, at the concourse of the refracted rays: thirdly, of a large nerve communicating between this membrane and the brain; without which, the action of light upon the membrane, however modified by the organ, would be lost to the purposes of sensation. The strength of the argument against chance derived, according to Paley, from a notion that he named relation and that later authors would term irreducible complexity. Paley wrote: When several different parts contribute to one effect, or, which is the same thing, when an effect is produced by the joint action of different instruments, the fitness of such parts or instruments to one another for the purpose of producing, by their united action, the effect, is what I call relation; and wherever this is observed in the works of nature or of man, it appears to me to carry along with it decisive evidence of understanding, intention, art…all depending upon the motions within, all upon the system of intermediate actions. Natural Theology was part of the canon at Cambridge for half a century after Paley's death. It thus was read by Darwin, who was an undergraduate student there between 1827 and 1831, with profit and “much delight.” Darwin was mindful of Paley's relation argument when in the Origin of Species he stated: “If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed, which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications, my theory would absolutely break down. But I can find out no such case.…We should be extremely cautious in concluding that an organ could not have been formed by transitional gradations of some kind.” In the 1990s several authors revived the argument from design. The proposition, once again, was that living beings manifest “intelligent design”—they are so diverse and complicated that they can be explained not as the outcome of natural processes but only as products of an “intelligent designer.” Some authors clearly equated this entity with the omnipotent God of Christianity and other monotheistic religions. Others, because they wished to see the theory of intelligent design taught in schools as an alternate to the theory of evolution, avoided all explicit reference to God in order to maintain the separation between religion and state. The call for an intelligent designer is predicated on the existence of irreducible complexity in organisms. In Michael Behe's book Darwin's Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution (1996), an irreducibly complex system is defined as being “composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning.” Contemporary intelligent-design proponents have argued that irreducibly complex systems cannot be the outcome of evolution. According to Behe, “Since natural selection can only choose systems that are already working, then if a biological system cannot be produced gradually it would have to arise as an integrated unit, in one fell swoop, for natural selection to have anything to act on.” In other words, unless all parts of the eye come simultaneously into existence, the eye cannot function; it does not benefit a precursor organism to have just a retina, or a lens, if the other parts are lacking. The human eye, they conclude, could not have evolved one small step at a time, in the piecemeal manner by which natural selection works. The theory of intelligent design has encountered many critics, not only among evolutionary scientists but also among theologians and religious authors. Evolutionists point out that organs and other components of living beings are not irreducibly complex—they do not come about suddenly, or in one fell swoop. The human eye did not appear suddenly in all its present complexity. Its formation required the integration of many genetic units, each improving the performance of preexisting, functionally less-perfect eyes. About 700 million years ago, the ancestors of today's vertebrates already had organs sensitive to light. Mere perception of light—and, later, various levels of vision ability—were beneficial to these organisms living in environments pervaded by sunlight. As is discussed more fully below in the section Diversity and extinction (evolution), different kinds of eyes have independently evolved at least 40 times in animals, which exhibit a full range, from very uncomplicated modifications that allow individual cells or simple animals to perceive the direction of light to the sophisticated vertebrate eye, passing through all sorts of organs intermediate in complexity. Evolutionists have shown that the examples of irreducibly complex systems cited by intelligent-design theorists—such as the biochemical mechanism of blood clotting (see coagulation) or the molecular rotary motor, called the flagellum, by which bacterial cells move—are not irreducible at all; rather, less-complex versions of the same systems can be found in today's organisms. Evolutionists have pointed out as well that imperfections and defects pervade the living world. In the human eye (eye, human), for example, the visual nerve fibres in the eye converge on an area of the retina to form the optic nerve and thus create a blind spot; squids and octopuses do not have this defect. Defective design seems incompatible with an omnipotent intelligent designer. Anticipating this criticism, Paley responded that “apparent blemishes…ought to be referred to some cause, though we be ignorant of it.” Modern intelligent-design theorists have made similar assertions; according to Behe, “The argument from imperfection overlooks the possibility that the designer might have multiple motives, with engineering excellence oftentimes relegated to a secondary role.” This statement, evolutionists have responded, may have theological validity, but it destroys intelligent design as a scientific hypothesis, because it provides it with an empirically impenetrable shield against predictions of how “intelligent” or “perfect” a design will be. Science tests its hypotheses by observing whether predictions derived from them are the case in the observable world. A hypothesis that cannot be tested empirically—that is, by observation or experiment—is not scientific. The implication of this line of reasoning for U.S. public schools has been recognized not only by scientists but also by nonscientists, including politicians and policy makers. The liberal U.S. senator Edward Kennedy wrote in 2002 that “intelligent design is not a genuine scientific theory and, therefore, has no place in the curriculum of our nation's public school science classes.” Scientists, moreover, have pointed out that not only do imperfections exist but so do dysfunctions, blunders, oddities, and cruelties prevail in the world of life. For this reason theologians and religious authors have criticized the theory of intelligent design, because it leads to conclusions about the nature of the designer at odds with the omniscience, omnipotence, and omnibenevolence that they, like Paley, identify as the attributes of the Creator. One example of a “blunder” is the human jaw, which for its size has too many teeth; the third molars, or wisdom teeth, often become impacted and need to be removed. Whereas many people would find it awkward, to say the least, to attribute to God a design that a capable human engineer would not even wish to claim, evolution gives a good account of this imperfection. As brain size increased over time in human ancestors, the concurrent remodeling of the skull entailed a reduction of the jaw so that the head of the fetus would continue to fit through the birth canal of the adult female. Evolution responds to an organism's needs not by optimal design but by tinkering, as it were—by slowly modifying existing structures through natural selection. Despite the modifications to the human jaw, the woman's birth canal remains much too narrow for easy passage of the fetal head, and many thousands of babies die during delivery as a result. Science makes this understandable as a consequence of the evolutionary enlargement of the human brain; females of other animals do not experience this difficulty. The world of life abounds in “cruel” behaviours. Numerous predators eat their prey alive; parasites destroy their living hosts from within; in many species of spiders and insects, the females devour their mates. Religious scholars in the past had struggled with such dysfunction and cruelty because they were difficult to explain by God's design. Evolution, in one respect, came to their rescue. A contemporary Protestant theologian called Darwin the “disguised friend,” and a Roman Catholic theologian wrote of “Darwin's gift to theology.” Both were acknowledging the irony that the theory of evolution, which at first had seemed to remove the need for God in the world, now was convincingly removing the need to explain the world's imperfections as outcomes of God's design. The science of evolution The process of evolution Evolution as a genetic function The concept of natural selection The central argument of Darwin's theory of evolution starts with the existence of hereditary variation. Experience with animal and plant breeding had demonstrated to Darwin that variations can be developed that are “useful to man.” So, he reasoned, variations must occur in nature that are favourable or useful in some way to the organism itself in the struggle for existence. Favourable variations are ones that increase chances for survival and procreation. Those advantageous variations are preserved and multiplied from generation to generation at the expense of less-advantageous ones. This is the process known as natural selection. The outcome of the process is an organism that is well adapted to its environment, and evolution often occurs as a consequence. Natural selection, then, can be defined as the differential reproduction of alternative hereditary variants, determined by the fact that some variants increase the likelihood that the organisms having them will survive and reproduce more successfully than will organisms carrying alternative variants. Selection may occur as a result of differences in survival, in fertility, in rate of development, in mating success, or in any other aspect of the life cycle. All of these differences can be incorporated under the term differential reproduction because all result in natural selection to the extent that they affect the number of progeny an organism leaves. Darwin maintained that competition for limited resources results in the survival of the most-effective competitors. Nevertheless, natural selection may occur not only as a result of competition but also as a result of some aspect of the physical environment, such as inclement weather. Moreover, natural selection would occur even if all the members of a population died at the same age, simply because some of them would have produced more offspring than others. Natural selection is quantified by a measure called Darwinian fitness or relative fitness. Fitness in this sense is the relative probability that a hereditary characteristic will be reproduced; that is, the degree of fitness is a measure of the reproductive efficiency of the characteristic. Biological evolution is the process of change and diversification of living things over time, and it affects all aspects of their lives— morphology (form and structure), physiology, behaviour, and ecology. Underlying these changes are changes in the hereditary materials. Hence, in genetic terms evolution consists of changes in the organism's hereditary makeup. Evolution can be seen as a two-step process. First, hereditary variation takes place; second, selection is made of those genetic variants that will be passed on most effectively to the following generations. Hereditary variation also entails two mechanisms—the spontaneous mutation of one variant into another and the sexual process that recombines those variants (see recombination) to form a multitude of variations. The variants that arise by mutation or recombination are not transmitted equally from one generation to another. Some may appear more frequently because they are favourable to the organism; the frequency of others may be determined by accidents of chance, called genetic drift. Genetic (gene) variation in populations The gene pool The gene pool is the sum total of all the genes and combinations of genes that occur in a population of organisms of the same species. It can be described by citing the frequencies of the alternative genetic constitutions. Consider, for example, a particular gene (which geneticists call a locus), such as the one determining the MN blood groups in humans. One form of the gene codes for the M blood group, while the other form codes for the N blood group; different forms of the same gene are called alleles. The MN gene pool of a particular population is specified by giving the frequencies of the alleles M and N. Thus, in the United States the M allele occurs in people of European descent with a frequency of 0.539 and the N allele with a frequency of 0.461—that is, 53.9 percent of the alleles in the population are M and 46.1 percent are N. In other populations these frequencies are different; for instance, the frequency of the M allele is 0.917 in Navajo Indians and 0.178 in Australian Aboriginals. The necessity of hereditary variation for evolutionary change to occur can be understood in terms of the gene pool. Assume, for instance, a population in which there is no variation at the gene locus that codes for the MN blood groups; only the M allele exists in all individuals. Evolution of the MN blood groups cannot take place in such a population, since the allelic frequencies have no opportunity to change from generation to generation. On the other hand, in populations in which both alleles M and N are present, evolutionary change is possible. Genetic variation and rate of evolution The more genetic variation that exists in a population, the greater the opportunity for evolution to occur. As the number of gene loci that are variable increases and as the number of alleles at each locus becomes greater, the likelihood grows that some alleles will change in frequency at the expense of their alternates. The British geneticist R.A. Fisher (Fisher, Sir Ronald Aylmer) mathematically demonstrated a direct correlation between the amount of genetic variation in a population and the rate of evolutionary change by natural selection. This demonstration is embodied in his fundamental theorem of natural selection (1930): “The rate of increase in fitness of any organism at any time is equal to its genetic variance in fitness at that time.” This theorem has been confirmed experimentally. One study employed different strains of Drosophila serrata, a species of vinegar fly from eastern Australia and New Guinea. Evolution in vinegar flies can be investigated by breeding them in separate “population cages” and finding out how populations change over many generations. Experimental populations were set up, with the flies living and reproducing in their isolated microcosms. Single-strain populations were established from flies collected either in New Guinea or in Australia; in addition, a mixed population was constituted by crossing these two strains of flies. The mixed population had the greater initial genetic variation, since it began with two different single-strain populations. To encourage rapid evolutionary change, the populations were manipulated such that the flies experienced intense competition for food and space. adaptation to the experimental environment was measured by periodically counting the number of individuals in the populations. Two results deserve notice. First, the mixed population had, at the end of the experiment, more flies than the single-strain populations. Second, and more relevant, the number of flies increased at a faster rate in the mixed population than in the single-strain populations. Evolutionary adaptation to the environment occurred in both types of population; both were able to maintain higher numbers as the generations progressed. But the rate of evolution was more rapid in the mixed group than in the single-strain groups. The greater initial amount of genetic variation made possible a faster rate of evolution. Measuring gene variability Because a population's potential for evolving is determined by its genetic variation, evolutionists are interested in discovering the extent of such variation in natural populations. It is readily apparent that plant and animal species are heterogeneous in all sorts of ways—in the flower colours and growth habits of plants, for instance, or the shell shapes and banding patterns of snails. Differences are more readily noticed among humans—in facial features, hair and skin colour, height, and weight—but such morphological differences are present in all groups of organisms. One problem with morphological variation is that it is not known how much is due to genetic factors and how much may result from environmental influences. Animal and plant breeders select for their experiments individuals or seeds that excel in desired attributes—in the protein content of corn (maize), for example, or the milk yield of cows. The selection is repeated generation after generation. If the population changes in the direction favoured by the breeder, it becomes clear that the original stock possessed genetic variation with respect to the selected trait. The results of artificial selection are impressive. Selection for high oil content in corn increased the oil content from less than 5 percent to more than 19 percent in 76 generations, while selection for low oil content reduced it to below 1 percent. Thirty years of selection for increased egg production in a flock of White Leghorn chickens increased the average yearly output of a hen from 125.6 to 249.6 eggs. Artificial selection has produced endless varieties of dog, cat, and horse breeds. The plants grown for food and fibre and the animals bred for food and transportation are all products of age-old or modern-day artificial selection. Since the late 20th century, scientists have used the techniques of molecular biology to modify or introduce genes for desired traits in a variety of organisms, including domestic plants and animals; this field has become known as genetic engineering or recombinant DNA technology. Improvements that in the past were achieved after tens of generations by artificial selection can now be accomplished much more effectively and rapidly (within a single generation) by molecular genetic technology. The success of artificial selection for virtually every trait and every organism in which it has been tried suggests that genetic variation is pervasive throughout natural populations. But evolutionists like to go one step farther and obtain quantitative estimates. Only since the 1960s, with the advances of molecular biology, have geneticists developed methods for measuring the extent of genetic variation in populations or among species of organisms. These methods consist essentially of taking a sample of genes and finding out how many are variable and how variable each one is. One simple way of measuring the variability of a gene locus is to ascertain what proportion of the individuals in a population are heterozygotes at that locus. In a heterozygous individual the two genes for a trait, one received from the mother and the other from the father, are different. The proportion of heterozygotes in the population is, therefore, the same as the probability that two genes taken at random from the gene pool are different. Techniques for determining heterozygosity have been used to investigate numerous species of plants and animals. Typically, insects and other invertebrates are more varied genetically than mammals and other vertebrates, and plants bred by outcrossing (crossing with relatively unrelated strains) exhibit more variation than those bred by self-pollination. But the amount of genetic variation is in any case astounding. Consider as an example humans, whose level of variation is about the same as that of other mammals. The human heterozygosity value at the level of proteins is stated as H = 0.067, which means that an individual is heterozygous at 6.7 percent of his genes, because the two genes at each locus encode slightly different proteins. The Human Genome Project demonstrated that there are at least 30,000 genes in humans. This means that a person is heterozygous at no fewer than 30,000 × 0.067 = 2,010 gene loci. An individual heterozygous at one locus (Aa) can produce two different kinds of sex cells, or gametes, one with each allele (A and a); an individual heterozygous at two loci (AaBb) can produce four kinds of gametes (AB, Ab, aB, and ab); an individual heterozygous at n loci can potentially produce 2n different gametes. Therefore, a typical human individual has the potential to produce 22,010, or approximately 10605 (1 with 605 zeros following), different kinds of gametes. That number is much larger than the estimated number of atoms in the universe, about 1080. It is clear, then, that every sex cell produced by a human being is genetically different from every other sex cell and, therefore, that no two persons who ever existed or will ever exist are likely to be genetically identical—with the exception of identical twins, which develop from a single fertilized ovum. The same conclusion applies to all organisms that reproduce sexually; every individual represents a unique genetic configuration that will likely never be repeated again. This enormous reservoir of genetic variation in natural populations provides virtually unlimited opportunities for evolutionary change in response to the environmental constraints and the needs of the organisms. The origin of genetic variation: mutations life originated about 3.5 billion years ago in the form of primordial organisms that were relatively simple and very small. All living things have evolved from these lowly beginnings. At present there are more than two million known species, which are widely diverse in size, shape, and way of life, as well as in the DNA sequences that contain their genetic information. What has produced the pervasive genetic variation within natural populations and the genetic differences among species? There must be some evolutionary means by which existing DNA sequences are changed and new sequences are incorporated into the gene pools of species. The information encoded in the nucleotide sequence of DNA is, as a rule, faithfully reproduced during replication, so that each replication results in two DNA molecules that are identical to each other and to the parent molecule. But heredity is not a perfectly conservative process; otherwise, evolution could not have taken place. Occasionally “mistakes,” or mutations, occur in the DNA molecule during replication, so that daughter cells differ from the parent cells in the sequence or in the amount of DNA. A mutation first appears in a single cell of an organism, but it is passed on to all cells descended from the first. Mutations can be classified into two categories—gene, or point, mutations, which affect only a few nucleotides within a gene, and chromosomal mutations, which either change the number of chromosomes or change the number or arrangement of genes on a chromosome. Gene mutations A gene mutation occurs when the nucleotide sequence of the DNA is altered and a new sequence is passed on to the offspring. The change may be either a substitution of one or a few nucleotides for others or an insertion or deletion of one or a few pairs of nucleotides. The four nucleotide bases of DNA, named adenine, cytosine, guanine, and thymine, are represented by the letters A, C, G, and T, respectively. (See nucleic acid; genetic code.) A gene that bears the code for constructing a protein molecule consists of a sequence of several thousand nucleotides, so that each segment of three nucleotides—called a triplet or codon—codes for one particular amino acid in the protein. The nucleotide sequence in the DNA is first transcribed into a molecule of messenger RNA (ribonucleic acid). The RNA, using a slightly different code (represented by the letters A, C, G, and U, the last letter representing the nucleotide base uracil), bears the message that determines which amino acid will be inserted into the protein's chain in the process of translation. Substitutions in the nucleotide sequence of a structural gene may result in changes in the amino acid sequence of the protein, although this is not always the case. The genetic code is redundant in that different triplets may hold the code for the same amino acid. Consider the triplet AUA in messenger RNA, which codes for the amino acid isoleucine (leucine). If the last A is replaced by C, the triplet still codes for isoleucine, but if it is replaced by G, it codes for methionine instead. A nucleotide substitution in the DNA that results in an amino acid substitution in the corresponding protein may or may not severely affect the biological function of the protein. Some nucleotide substitutions change a codon for an amino acid into a signal to terminate translation, and those mutations are likely to have harmful effects. If, for instance, the second U in the triplet UUA, which codes for leucine, is replaced by A, the triplet becomes UAA, a “terminator” codon; the result is that the triplets following this codon in the DNA sequence are not translated into amino acids. Additions or deletions of nucleotides within the DNA sequence of a structural gene often result in a greatly altered sequence of amino acids in the coded protein. The addition or deletion of one or two nucleotides shifts the “reading frame” of the nucleotide sequence all along the way from the point of the insertion or deletion to the end of the molecule. To illustrate, assume that the DNA segment …CATCATCATCATCAT… is read in groups of three as …CAT-CAT-CAT-CAT-CAT…. If a nucleotide base—say, T—is inserted after the first C of the segment, the segment will then be read as …CTA-TCA-TCA-TCA-TCA…. From the point of the insertion onward, the sequence of encoded amino acids is altered. If, however, a total of three nucleotides is either added or deleted, the original reading frame will be maintained in the rest of the sequence. Additions or deletions of nucleotides in numbers other than three or multiples of three are called frameshift mutations. Gene mutations can occur spontaneously—that is, without being intentionally caused by humans. They can also be induced by ultraviolet light, X rays, and other high-frequency electromagnetic radiation, as well as by exposure to certain mutagenic chemicals, such as mustard gas. The consequences of gene mutations may range from negligible to lethal. Mutations that change one or even several amino acids may have a small or undetectable effect on the organism's ability to survive and reproduce if the essential biological function of the coded protein is not hindered. But where an amino acid substitution affects the active site of an enzyme or modifies in some other way an essential function of a protein, the impact may be severe. Newly arisen mutations are more likely to be harmful than beneficial to their carriers, because mutations are random events with respect to adaptation—that is, their occurrence is independent of any possible consequences. The allelic variants present in an existing population have already been subject to natural selection. They are present in the population because they improve the adaptation of their carriers, and their alternative alleles have been eliminated or kept at low frequencies by natural selection. A newly arisen mutant is likely to have been preceded by an identical mutation in the previous history of a population. If the previous mutant no longer exists in the population, it is a sign that the new mutant is not beneficial to the organism and is likely also to be eliminated. This proposition can be illustrated with an analogy. Consider a sentence whose words have been chosen because together they express a certain idea. If single letters or words are replaced with others at random, most changes will be unlikely to improve the meaning of the sentence; very likely they will destroy it. The nucleotide sequence of a gene has been “edited” into its present form by natural selection because it “makes sense.” If the sequence is changed at random, the “meaning” rarely will be improved and often will be hampered or destroyed. Occasionally, however, a new mutation may increase the organism's adaptation. The probability of such an event's happening is greater when organisms colonize a new territory or when environmental (environment) changes confront a population with new challenges. In these cases the established adaptation of a population is less than optimal, and there is greater opportunity for new mutations to be better adaptive. The consequences of mutations depend on the environment. Increased melanin pigmentation may be advantageous to inhabitants of tropical Africa, where dark skin protects them from the Sun's ultraviolet radiation, but it is not beneficial in Scandinavia, where the intensity of sunlight is low and light skin facilitates the synthesis of vitamin D. Mutation rates have been measured in a great variety of organisms, mostly for mutants that exhibit conspicuous effects. Mutation rates are generally lower in bacteria and other microorganisms than in more complex species. In humans and other multicellular organisms, the rate typically ranges from about 1 per 100,000 to 1 per 1,000,000 gametes. There is, however, considerable variation from gene to gene as well as from organism to organism. Although mutation rates are low, new mutants appear continuously in nature, because there are many individuals in every species and many gene loci in every individual. The process of mutation provides each generation with many new genetic variations. Thus, it is not surprising to see that, when new environmental challenges arise, species are able to adapt to them. More than 200 insect and rodent species, for example, have developed resistance to the pesticide DDT in parts of the world where spraying has been intense. Although these animals had never before encountered this synthetic compound, they adapted to it rapidly by means of mutations that allowed them to survive in its presence. Similarly, many species of moths and butterflies in industrialized regions have shown an increase in the frequency of individuals with dark wings in response to environmental pollution, an adaptation known as industrial melanism (see below Directional selection (evolution)). The resistance of disease-causing bacteria and parasites to antibiotics and other drugs is a consequence of the same process. When an individual receives an antibiotic that specifically kills the bacteria causing the disease—say, tuberculosis—the immense majority of the bacteria die, but one in a million may have a mutation that provides resistance to the antibiotic. These resistant bacteria will survive and multiply, and the antibiotic will no longer cure the disease. This is the reason that modern medicine treats bacterial diseases with cocktails of antibiotics. If the incidence of a mutation conferring resistance for a given antibiotic is one in a million, the incidence of one bacterium carrying three mutations, each conferring resistance to one of three antibiotics, is one in a trillion; such bacteria are far less likely to exist in any infected individual. Chromosomal mutations chromosomes, which carry the hereditary material, or DNA, are contained in the nucleus of each cell. Chromosomes come in pairs, with one member of each pair inherited from each parent. The two members of a pair are called homologous chromosomes. Each cell of an organism and all individuals of the same species have, as a rule, the same number of chromosomes. The reproductive cells ( gametes) are an exception; they have only half as many chromosomes as the body (somatic) cells. But the number, size, and organization of chromosomes varies between species. The parasitic nematode Parascaris univalens has only one pair of chromosomes, whereas many species of butterflies have more than 100 pairs and some ferns more than 600. Even closely related organisms may vary considerably in the number of chromosomes. Species of spiny rats of the South American genus Proechimys range from 12 to 31 chromosome pairs. Changes in the number, size, or organization of chromosomes within a species are termed chromosomal mutations, chromosomal abnormalities, or chromosomal aberrations. Changes in number may occur by the fusion of two chromosomes into one, by fission of one chromosome into two, or by addition or subtraction of one or more whole chromosomes or sets of chromosomes. (The condition in which an organism acquires one or more additional sets of chromosomes is called polyploidy.) Changes in the structure of chromosomes may occur by inversion, when a chromosomal segment rotates 180 degrees within the same location; by duplication, when a segment is added; by deletion, when a segment is lost; or by translocation, when a segment changes from one location to another in the same or a different chromosome. These are the processes by which chromosomes evolve. Inversions, translocations, fusions, and fissions do not change the amount of DNA. The importance of these mutations in evolution is that they change the linkage relationships between genes. Genes that were closely linked to each other become separated and vice versa; this can affect their expression because genes are often transcribed sequentially, two or more at a time (see heredity: Linkage of traits (heredity)). Dynamics of genetic change Genetic equilibrium: the Hardy-Weinberg law Genetic variation is present throughout natural populations of organisms. This variation is sorted out in new ways in each generation by the process of sexual reproduction, which recombines the chromosomes inherited from the two parents during the formation of the gametes that produce the following generation. But heredity by itself does not change gene frequencies. This principle is stated by the Hardy-Weinberg law, so called because it was independently discovered in 1908 by the English mathematician G.H. Hardy (Hardy, Godfrey Harold) and the German physician Wilhelm Weinberg. The Hardy-Weinberg law describes the genetic equilibrium in a population by means of an algebraic equation. It states that genotypes, the genetic constitution of individual organisms, exist in certain frequencies that are a simple function of the allelic frequencies—namely, the square expansion of the sum of the allelic frequencies. If there are two alleles, A and a, at a gene locus, three genotypes will be possible: AA, Aa, and aa. If the frequencies of the alleles A and a are p and q, respectively, the equilibrium frequencies of the three genotypes will be given by (p + q)2 = p2 + 2pq + q2 for AA, Aa, and aa, respectively. The genotype equilibrium frequencies for any number of alleles are derived in the same way. If there are three alleles, A1, A2, and A3, with frequencies p, q, and r, the equilibrium frequencies corresponding to the six possible genotypes (shown in parentheses) will be calculated as follows: The figure--> shows how the law operates in a situation with just two alleles. Across the top and down the left side are the frequencies in the parental generation of the two alleles, p for A and q for a. As shown in the lower right of the figure, the probabilities of the three possible genotypes in the following generation are products of the probabilities of the corresponding alleles in the parents. The probability of genotype AA among the progeny is the probability p that allele A will be present in the paternal gamete multiplied by the probability p that allele A will be present in the maternal gamete, or p2. Similarly, the probability of the genotype aa is q2. The genotype Aa can arise when A from the father combines with a from the mother, which will occur with a frequency pq, or when a from the father combines with A from the mother, which also has a probability of pq; the result is a total probability of 2pq for the frequency of the Aa genotype in the progeny. There is no change in the allele equilibrium frequencies from one generation to the next. The frequency of the A allele among the offspring is the frequency of the AA genotype (because all alleles in these individuals are A alleles) plus half the frequency of the Aa genotype (because half the alleles in these individuals are A alleles), or p2 + pq = p(p + q) = p (because p + q = 1). Similarly, the frequency of the a allele among the offspring is given by q2 + pq = q(q + p) = q. These are precisely the frequencies of the alleles in the parents. The genotype equilibrium frequencies are obtained by the Hardy-Weinberg law on the assumption that there is random mating—that is, the probability of a particular kind of mating is the same as the frequency of the genotypes of the two mating individuals. For example, the probability of an AA female mating with an aa male must be p2 (the frequency of AA) times q2 (the frequency of aa). Random mating can occur with respect to most gene loci even though mates may be chosen according to particular characteristics. People, for example, choose their spouses according to all sorts of preferences concerning looks, personality, and the like. But concerning the majority of genes, people's marriages are essentially random. Assortative (assortative mating), or selective, mating takes place when the choice of mates is not random. Marriages in the United States, for example, are assortative with respect to many social factors, so that members of any one social group tend to marry members of their own group more often, and people from a different group less often, than would be expected from random mating. Consider the sensitive social issue of interracial marriage (miscegenation) in a hypothetical community in which 80 percent of the population is white and 20 percent is black. With random mating, 32 percent (2 × 0.80 × 0.20 = 0.32) of all marriages would be interracial, whereas only 4 percent (0.20 × 0.20 = 0.04) would be marriages between two blacks. These statistical expectations depart from typical observations even in modern society, as a result of persistent social customs that for evolutionists are examples of assortative mating. The most extreme form of assortative mating is self-fertilization, which occurs rarely in animals but is a common form of reproduction in many plant groups. The Hardy-Weinberg law assumes that gene frequencies remain constant from generation to generation—that there is no gene mutation or natural selection and that populations are very large. But these assumptions are not correct; indeed, if they were, evolution could not occur. Why, then, is the law significant if its assumptions do not hold true in nature? The answer is that it plays in evolutionary studies a role similar to that of Newton's first law of motion (Newton's laws of motion) in mechanics. Newton's first law says that a body not acted upon by a net external force remains at rest or maintains a constant velocity. In fact, there are always external forces acting upon physical objects, but the first law provides the starting point for the application of other laws. Similarly, organisms are subject to mutation, selection, and other processes that change gene frequencies, but the effects of these processes can be calculated by using the Hardy-Weinberg law as the starting point. Processes of gene-frequency change Mutation The allelic variations that make evolution possible are generated by the process of mutation, but new mutations change gene frequencies very slowly, because mutation rates are low. Assume that the gene allele A1 mutates to allele A2 at a rate m per generation and that at a given time the frequency of A1 is p. In the next generation, a fraction m of all A1 alleles become A2 alleles. The frequency of A1 in the next generation will then be reduced by the fraction of mutated alleles (pm), or p1 = p − pm = p(1 − m). After t generations the frequency of A1 will be pt = p(1 − m)t. If the mutations continue, the frequency of A1 alleles will gradually decrease, because a fraction of them change every generation to A2. If the process continues indefinitely, the A1 allele will eventually disappear, although the process is slow. If the mutation rate is 10−5 (1 in 100,000) per gene per generation, about 2,000 generations will be required for the frequency of A1 to change from 0.50 to 0.49 and about 10,000 generations for it to change from 0.10 to 0.09. Moreover, gene mutations are reversible: the allele A2 may also mutate to A1. Assume that A1 mutates to A2 at a rate m, as before, and that A2 mutates to A1 at a rate n per generation. If at a certain time the frequencies of A1 and A2 are p and q, respectively, after one generation the frequency of A1 will be p1 = p − pm + qn. A fraction pm of allele A1 changes to A2, but a fraction qn of the A2 alleles changes to A1. The conditions for equilibrium occur when pm = qn, or p = n/(m + n). Suppose that the mutation rates are m = 10−5 and n = 10−6; then, at equilibrium, p = 10−6/(10−5 + 10−6) = 1/(10 + 1) = 0.09, and q = 0.91. Changes in gene frequencies due to mutation occur, therefore, at rates even slower than was suggested above, because forward and backward mutations counteract each other. In any case, allelic frequencies usually are not in mutational (mutation) equilibrium, because some alleles are favoured over others by natural selection. The equilibrium frequencies are then decided by the interaction between mutation and selection, with selection usually having the greater consequence. Gene flow gene flow, or gene migration, takes place when individuals migrate from one population to another and interbreed with its members. Gene frequencies are not changed for the species as a whole, but they change locally whenever different populations have different allele frequencies. In general, the greater the difference in allele frequencies between the resident and the migrant individuals, and the larger the number of migrants, the greater effect the migrants have in changing the genetic constitution of the resident population. Suppose that a proportion of all reproducing individuals in a population are migrants and that the frequency of allele A1 is p in the population but pm among the migrants. The change in gene frequency, Δp, in the next generation will be Δp = m(pm − p). If the migration rate persists for a number t of generations, the frequency of A1 will be given by pt = (1 −m)t(p − pm) + pm. genetic drift Gene frequencies can change from one generation to another by a process of pure chance known as genetic drift. This occurs because the number of individuals in any population is finite, and thus the frequency of a gene may change in the following generation by accidents of sampling, just as it is possible to get more or fewer than 50 “heads” in 100 throws of a coin simply by chance. The magnitude of the gene frequency changes due to genetic drift is inversely related to the size of the population—the larger the number of reproducing individuals, the smaller the effects of genetic drift. This inverse relationship between sample size and magnitude of sampling errors can be illustrated by referring again to tossing a coin. When a penny is tossed twice, two heads are not surprising. But it will be surprising, and suspicious, if 20 tosses all yield heads. The proportion of heads obtained in a series of throws approaches closer to 0.5 as the number of throws grows larger. The relationship is the same in populations, although the important value here is not the actual number of individuals in the population but the “effective” population size. This is the number of individuals that produce offspring, because only reproducing individuals transmit their genes to the following generation. It is not unusual, in plants as well as animals, for some individuals to have large numbers of progeny while others have none. In marine seals, antelopes, baboons, and many other mammals, for example, a dominant male may keep a large harem of females at the expense of many other males who can find no mates. It often happens that the effective population size is substantially smaller than the number of individuals in any one generation. The effects of genetic drift in changing gene frequencies from one generation to the next are quite small in most natural populations, which generally consist of thousands of reproducing individuals. The effects over many generations are more important. Indeed, in the absence of other processes of change (such as natural selection and mutation), populations would eventually become fixed, having one allele at each locus after the gradual elimination of all others. With genetic drift as the only force in operation, the probability of a given allele's eventually reaching a frequency of 1 would be precisely the frequency of the allele—that is, an allele with a frequency of 0.8 would have an 80 percent chance of ultimately becoming the only allele present in the population. The process would, however, take a long time, because increases and decreases are likely to alternate with equal probability. More important, natural selection and other processes change gene frequencies in ways not governed by pure chance, so that no allele has an opportunity to become fixed as a consequence of genetic drift alone. Genetic drift can have important evolutionary consequences when a new population becomes established by only a few individuals—a phenomenon known as the founder principle. Islands, lakes, and other isolated ecological sites are often colonized by one or very few seeds or animals of a species, which are transported there passively by wind, in the fur of larger animals, or in some other way. The allelic frequencies present in these few colonizers are likely to differ at many loci from those in the population they left, and those differences have a lasting impact on the evolution of the new population. The founder principle is one reason that species in neighbouring islands, such as those in the Hawaiian archipelago, are often more heterogeneous than species in comparable continental areas adjacent to one another. Climatic or other conditions, if unfavourable, may on occasion drastically reduce the number of individuals in a population and even threaten it with extinction. Such occasional reductions are called population bottlenecks. The populations may later recover their typical size, but the allelic frequencies may have been considerably altered and thereby affect the future evolution of the species. Bottlenecks are more likely in relatively large animals and plants than in smaller ones, because populations of large organisms typically consist of fewer individuals. Primitive human populations of the past were subdivided into many small tribes that were time and again decimated by disease, war, and other disasters. Differences among current human populations in the allele frequencies of many genes—such as those determining the ABO and other blood groups—may have arisen at least in part as a consequence of bottlenecks in ancestral populations. Persistent population bottlenecks may reduce the overall genetic variation so greatly as to alter future evolution and endanger the survival of the species. A well-authenticated case is that of the cheetah, where no allelic variation whatsoever has been found among the many scores of gene loci studied. The operation of natural selection in populations Natural selection as a process of genetic change natural selection refers to any reproductive bias favouring some genes or genotypes over others. Natural selection promotes the adaptation of organisms to the environments in which they live; any hereditary variant that improves the ability to survive and reproduce in an environment will increase in frequency over the generations, precisely because the organisms carrying such a variant will leave more descendants than those lacking it. Hereditary variants, favourable or not to the organisms, arise by mutation. Unfavourable ones are eventually eliminated by natural selection; their carriers leave no descendants or leave fewer than those carrying alternative variants. Favourable mutations accumulate over the generations. The process continues indefinitely because the environments that organisms inhabit are forever changing. Environments change physically—in their climate, configuration, and so on—but also biologically, because the predators, parasites, competitors, and food sources with which an organism interacts are themselves evolving. Mutation, gene flow, and genetic drift are random processes with respect to adaptation; they change gene frequencies without regard for the consequences that such changes may have in the ability of the organisms to survive and reproduce. If these were the only processes of evolutionary change, the organization of living things would gradually disintegrate. The effects of such processes alone would be analogous to those of a mechanic who changed parts in an automobile engine at random, with no regard for the role of the parts in the engine. Natural selection keeps the disorganizing effects of mutation and other processes in check because it multiplies beneficial mutations and eliminates harmful ones. Natural selection accounts not only for the preservation and improvement of the organization of living beings but also for their diversity. In different localities or in different circumstances, natural selection favours different traits, precisely those that make the organisms well adapted to their particular circumstances and ways of life. The parameter used to measure the effects of natural selection is fitness (see above The concept of natural selection (evolution)), which can be expressed as an absolute or as a relative value. Consider a population consisting at a certain locus of three genotypes: A1A1, A1A2, and A2A2. Assume that on the average each A1A1 and each A1A2 individual produces one offspring but that each A2A2 individual produces two. One could use the average number of progeny left by each genotype as a measure of that genotype's absolute fitness and calculate the changes in gene frequency that would occur over the generations. (This, of course, requires knowing how many of the progeny survive to adulthood and reproduce.) Evolutionists, however, find it mathematically more convenient to use relative fitness values—which they represent with the letter w—in most calculations. They usually assign the value 1 to the genotype with the highest reproductive efficiency and calculate the other relative fitness values proportionally. For the example just used, the relative fitness of the A2A2 genotype would be w = 1 and that of each of the other two genotypes would be w = 0.5. A parameter related to fitness is the selection coefficient, often represented by the letter s, which is defined as s = 1 − w. The selection coefficient is a measure of the reduction in fitness of a genotype. The selection coefficients in the example are s = 0 for A2A2 and s = 0.5 for A1A1 and for A1A2. The different ways in which natural selection affects gene frequencies are illustrated by the following examples. Selection against one of the homozygotes (homozygote) Suppose that one homozygous genotype, A2A2, has lower fitness than the other two genotypes, A1A1 and A1A2. (This is the situation in many human diseases, such as phenylketonuria 【PKU】 and sickle cell anemia, that are inherited in a recessive fashion and that require the presence of two deleterious mutant alleles for the trait to manifest.) The heterozygotes and the homozygotes for the normal allele (A1) have equal fitness, higher than that of the homozygotes for the deleterious mutant allele (A2). Call the fitness of these latter homozygotes 1 − s (the fitness of the other two genotypes is 1), and let p be the frequency of A1 and q the frequency of A2. It can be shown that the frequency of A2 will decrease each generation by an amount given by Δq = −spq2/(1 − sq2). The deleterious allele will continuously decrease in frequency until it has been eliminated. The rate of elimination is fastest when s = 1 (i.e., when the relative fitness w = 0); this occurs with fatal diseases, such as untreated PKU, when the homozygotes die before the age of reproduction. Because of new mutations, the elimination of a deleterious allele is never complete. A dynamic equilibrium frequency will exist when the number of new alleles produced by mutation is the same as the number eliminated by selection. If the mutation rate at which the deleterious allele arises is u, the equilibrium frequency for a deleterious allele that is recessive is given approximately by q = √u/s, which, if s = 1, reduces to q = √u. The mutation rate for many human recessive diseases is about 1 in 100,000 (u = 10−5). If the disease is fatal, the equilibrium frequency becomes q √(10−5) = 0.003, or about 1 recessive lethal mutant allele for every 300 normal alleles. That is roughly the frequency in human populations of alleles that in homozygous individuals, such as those with PKU, cause death before adulthood. The equilibrium frequency for a deleterious, but not lethal, recessive allele is much higher. albinism, for example, is due to a recessive gene. The reproductive efficiency of albinos is, on average, about 0.9 that of normal individuals. Therefore, s = 0.1 and q = √u/s = √(10−5/10−1) = 0.01, or 1 in 100 genes rather than 1 in 300 as for a lethal allele. For deleterious dominant alleles, the mutation-selection equilibrium frequency is given by p = u/s, which for fatal genes becomes p = u. If the gene is lethal even in single copy, all the genes are eliminated by selection in the same generation in which they arise, and the frequency of the gene in the population is the frequency with which it arises by mutation. One deleterious condition that is caused by a dominant allele present at low frequencies in human populations is achondroplasia, the most common cause of dwarfism. Because of abnormal growth of the long bones, achondroplastics have short, squat, often deformed limbs, along with bulging skulls. The mutation rate from the normal allele to the achondroplasia allele is about 5 × 10−5. Achondroplastics reproduce only 20 percent as efficiently as normal individuals; hence, s = 0.8. The equilibrium frequency of the mutant allele can therefore be calculated as p = u/s = 6.25 × 10−5. Overdominance In many instances heterozygotes have a higher degree of fitness than homozygotes for one or the other allele. This situation, known as heterosis or overdominance, leads to the stable coexistence of both alleles in the population and hence contributes to the widespread genetic variation found in populations of most organisms. The model situation is: It is assumed that s and t are positive numbers between 0 and 1, so that the fitnesses of the two homozygotes are somewhat less than 1. It is not difficult to show that the change in frequency per generation of allele A2 is Δq = pq(sp − tq)/(1 − sp2 − tq2). An equilibrium will exist when Δq = 0 (gene frequencies no longer change); this will happen when sp = tq, at which the numerator of the expression for Δq will be 0. The condition sp = tq can be rewritten as s(1 − q) = tq (when p + q = 1), which leads to q = s/(s + t). If the fitnesses of the two homozygotes are known, it is possible to infer the allele equilibrium frequencies. One of many well-investigated examples of overdominance in animals is the colour polymorphism that exists in the marine copepod crustacean Tisbe reticulata. Three populations of colour variants (morphs) are found in the lagoon of Venice; they are known as violacea (homozygous genotype VVVV), maculata (homozygous genotype VMVM), and violacea-maculata (heterozygous genotype VVVM). The colour polymorphism persists in the lagoon because the heterozygotes survive better than either of the two homozygotes. In laboratory experiments, the fitness of the three genotypes depends on the degree of crowding, as shown by the following comparison of their relative fitnesses: The greater the crowding—with more competition for resources—the greater the superiority of the heterozygotes. (In this example, the colour trait serves a genetic marker—individuals heterozygous for the marker have higher fitness, but whether this is due to the colour per se is not known.) A particularly interesting example of heterozygote superiority among humans is provided by the gene responsible for sickle cell anemia. Human hemoglobin in adults is for the most part hemoglobin A, a four-component molecule consisting of two α and two β hemoglobin chains. The gene bA codes for the normal β hemoglobin chain, which consists of 146 amino acids. A mutant allele of this gene, bS, causes the β chain to have in the sixth position the amino acid valine instead of glutamic acid. This seemingly minor substitution modifies the properties of hemoglobin so that homozygotes with the mutant allele, HbSHbS, suffer from a severe form of anemia that in most cases leads to death before the age of reproduction. The HbS allele occurs in some African and Asian populations with a high frequency. This formerly was puzzling because the severity of the anemia, representing a strong natural selection against homozygotes, should have eliminated the defective allele. But researchers noticed that the HbS allele occurred at high frequency precisely in regions of the world where a particularly severe form of malaria, which is caused by the parasite Plasmodium falciparum, was endemic. It was hypothesized that the heterozygotes, HbAHbS, were resistant to malaria, whereas the homozygotes HbAHbA were not. In malaria-infested regions then the heterozygotes survived better than either of the homozygotes, which were more likely to die from either malaria (HbAHbA homozygotes) or anemia (HbSHbS homozygotes). This hypothesis has been confirmed in various ways. Most significant is that most hospital patients suffering from severe or fatal forms of malaria are homozygotes HbAHbA. In a study of 100 children who died from malaria, only 1 was found to be a heterozygote, whereas 22 were expected to be so according to the frequency of the HbS allele in the population. Fitnesses of the three genotypes at the sickle cell anemia locus in a population from NigeriaThe table (Fitnesses of the three genotypes at the sickle cell anemia locus in a population from Nigeria) shows how the relative fitness of the three β-chain genotypes can be calculated from their distribution among the Yoruba people of Ibadan, Nigeria. The frequency of the HbS allele among adults is estimated as q = 0.1232. According to the Hardy-Weinberg law, the three genotypes will be formed at conception in the frequencies p2, 2pq, and q2, which are the expected frequencies given in the table. The ratios of the observed frequencies among adults to the expected frequencies give the relative survival efficiency of the three genotypes. These are divided by their largest value (1.12) in order to obtain the relative fitness of the genotypes. Sickle cell anemia reduces the probability of survival of the HbSHbS homozygotes to 13 percent of that of the heterozygotes. On the other hand, malaria infection reduces the survival probability of the homozygotes for the normal allele, HbAHbA, to 88 percent of that of the heterozygotes. Frequency-dependent selection The fitness of genotypes can change when the environmental conditions change. White fur may be protective to a bear living on the Arctic snows but not to one living in a Russian forest; there an allele coding for brown pigmentation may be favoured over one that codes for white. The environment of an organism includes not only the climate and other physical features but also the organisms of the same or different species with which it is associated. Changes in genotypic fitness are associated with the density of the organisms present. Insects and other short-lived organisms experience enormous yearly oscillations in density. Some genotypes may possess high fitness in the spring, when the population is rapidly expanding, because such genotypes yield more prolific individuals. Other genotypes may be favoured during the summer, when populations are dense, because these genotypes make for better competitors, ones more successful at securing limited food resources. Still others may be at an advantage during the long winter months, because they increase the population's hardiness, or ability to withstand the inclement conditions that kill most members of the other genotypes. The fitness of genotypes can also vary according to their relative numbers, and genotype frequencies may change as a consequence. This is known as frequency-dependent selection. Particularly interesting is the situation in which genotypic fitnesses are inversely related to their frequencies. Assume that two genotypes, A and B, have fitnesses related to their frequencies in such a way that the fitness of either genotype increases when its frequency decreases and vice versa. When A is rare, its fitness is high, and therefore A increases in frequency. As it becomes more and more common, however, the fitness of A gradually decreases, so that its increase in frequency eventually comes to a halt. A stable polymorphism occurs at the frequency where the two genotypes, A and B, have identical fitnesses. In natural populations of animals and plants, frequency-dependent selection is very common and may contribute importantly to the maintenance of genetic polymorphism. In the vinegar fly Drosophila pseudoobscura, for example, three genotypes exist at the gene locus that codes for the metabolically important enzyme malate dehydrogenase—the homozygous SS and FF and the heterozygous SF. When the SS homozygotes represent 90 percent of the population, they have a fitness about two-thirds that of the heterozygotes, SF. But when the SS homozygotes represent only 10 percent of the population, their fitness is more than double that of the heterozygotes. Similarly, the fitness of the FF homozygotes relative to the heterozygotes increases from less than half to nearly double as their frequency goes from 90 to 10 percent. All three genotypes have equal fitnesses when the frequency of the S allele, represented by p, is about 0.70, so that there is a stable polymorphism with frequencies p2 = 0.49 for SS, 2pq = 0.42 for SF, and q2 = 0.09 for FF. Frequency-dependent selection may arise because the environment is heterogeneous and because different genotypes can better exploit different subenvironments. When a genotype is rare, the subenvironments that it exploits better will be relatively abundant. But as the genotype becomes common, its favoured subenvironment becomes saturated. That genotype must then compete for resources in subenvironments that are optimal for other genotypes. It follows then that a mixture of genotypes exploits the environmental resources better than a single genotype. This has been extensively demonstrated. When the three Drosophila genotypes mentioned above were mixed in a single population, the average number of individuals that developed per unit of food was 45.6. This was greater than the number of individuals that developed when only one of the genotypes was present, which averaged 41.1 for SS, 40.2 for SF, and 37.1 for FF. Plant breeders know that mixed plantings (a mixture of different strains) are more productive than single stands (plantings of one strain only), although farmers avoid them for reasons such as increased harvesting costs. Sexual (sex) preferences can also lead to frequency-dependent selection. It has been demonstrated in some insects, birds, mammals, and other organisms that the mates preferred are precisely those that are rare. People also appear to experience this rare-mate advantage—blonds may seem attractively exotic to brunets, or brunets to blonds. Types of selection Stabilizing selection Natural selection can be studied by analyzing its effects on changing gene frequencies, but it can also be explored by examining its effects on the observable characteristics—or phenotypes—of individuals in a population. Distribution scales of phenotypic traits such as height, weight, number of progeny, or longevity typically show greater numbers of individuals with intermediate values and fewer and fewer toward the extremes—this is the so-called normal distribution. When individuals with intermediate phenotypes are favoured and extreme phenotypes are selected against, the selection is said to be stabilizing. (See the left column of the figure-->.) The range and distribution of phenotypes then remains approximately the same from one generation to another. Stabilizing selection is very common. The individuals that survive and reproduce more successfully are those that have intermediate phenotypic values. Mortality among newborn infants, for example, is highest when they are either very small or very large; infants of intermediate size have a greater chance of surviving. Stabilizing selection is often noticeable after artificial selection. Breeders choose chickens that produce larger eggs, cows that yield more milk, and corn with higher protein content. But the selection must be continued or reinstated from time to time, even after the desired goals have been achieved. If it is stopped altogether, natural selection gradually takes effect and turns the traits back toward their original intermediate value. As a result of stabilizing selection, populations often maintain a steady genetic constitution with respect to many traits. This attribute of populations is called genetic homeostasis. Directional selection The distribution of phenotypes in a population sometimes changes systematically in a particular direction. (See the centre column of the figure-->.) The physical and biological aspects of the environment are continuously changing, and over long periods of time the changes may be substantial. The climate and even the configuration of the land or waters vary incessantly. Changes also take place in the biotic conditions—that is, in the other organisms present, whether predators, prey, parasites, or competitors. Genetic changes occur as a consequence, because the genotypic fitnesses may shift so that different sets of alleles are favoured. The opportunity for directional selection also arises when organisms colonize new environments where the conditions are different from those of their original habitat. In addition, the appearance of a new favourable allele or a new genetic combination may prompt directional changes as the new genetic constitution replaces the preexisting one. The process of directional selection takes place in spurts. The replacement of one genetic constitution with another changes the genotypic fitnesses at other loci, which then change in their allelic frequencies, thereby stimulating additional changes, and so on in a cascade of consequences. Directional selection is possible only if there is genetic variation with respect to the phenotypic traits under selection. Natural populations contain large stores of genetic variation, and these are continuously replenished by additional new variants that arise by mutation. The nearly universal success of artificial selection and the rapid response of natural populations to new environmental challenges are evidence that existing variation provides the necessary materials for directional selection. In modern times human actions have been an important stimulus to this type of selection. Human activity transforms the environments of many organisms, which rapidly respond to the new environmental challenges through directional selection. Well-known instances are the many cases of insect resistance to pesticides (pesticide), which are synthetic substances not present in the natural environment. When a new insecticide is first applied to control a pest, the results are encouraging because a small amount of the insecticide is sufficient to bring the pest organism under control. As time passes, however, the amount required to achieve a certain level of control must be increased again and again until finally it becomes ineffective or economically impractical. This occurs because organisms become resistant to the pesticide through directional selection. The resistance of the housefly, Musca domestica, to DDT was first reported in 1947. Resistance to one or more pesticides has since been recorded in several hundred species of insects and mites. Another example is the phenomenon of industrial melanism (mentioned above in the section Gene mutations (evolution)), which is exemplified by the gradual darkening of the wings of many species of moths and butterflies living in woodlands darkened by industrial pollution. The best-investigated case is the peppered moth, Biston betularia, of England. Until the middle of the 19th century, these moths were uniformly peppered light gray. Darkly pigmented variants were detected first in 1848 in Manchester and shortly afterward in other industrial regions where the vegetation was blackened by soot and other pollutants. By the middle of the 20th century, the dark varieties had almost completely replaced the lightly pigmented forms in many polluted areas, while in unpolluted regions light moths continued to be the most common. The shift from light to dark moths was an example of directional selection brought about by bird predators. On lichen-covered tree trunks, the light-gray moths are well camouflaged, whereas the dark ones are conspicuously visible and therefore fall victim to the birds. The opposite is the case on trees darkened by pollution. Over geologic time, directional selection leads to major changes in morphology and ways of life. Evolutionary changes that persist in a more or less continuous fashion over long periods of time are known as evolutionary trends. Directional evolutionary changes increased the cranial capacity of the human (Homo sapiens) lineage from the small brain of Australopithecus—human ancestors of three million years ago—which was less than 500 cc in volume, to a brain nearly three times as large in modern humans. The evolution of the horse from more than 50 million years ago to modern times is another well-studied example of directional selection. Diversifying selection Two or more divergent phenotypes in an environment may be favoured simultaneously by diversifying selection. (See the right column of the figure-->.) No natural environment is homogeneous; rather, the environment of any plant or animal population is a mosaic consisting of more or less dissimilar subenvironments. There is heterogeneity with respect to climate, food resources, and living space. Also, the heterogeneity may be temporal, with change occurring over time, as well as spatial. Species cope with environmental heterogeneity in diverse ways. One strategy is genetic monomorphism, the selection of a generalist genotype that is well adapted to all the subenvironments encountered by the species. Another strategy is genetic polymorphism, the selection of a diversified gene pool that yields different genotypes, each adapted to a specific subenvironment. There is no single plan that prevails in nature. Sometimes the most efficient strategy is genetic monomorphism to confront temporal heterogeneity but polymorphism to confront spatial heterogeneity. If the environment changes in time or if it is unstable relative to the life span of the organisms, each individual will have to face diverse environments appearing one after the other. A series of genotypes, each well adapted to one or another of the conditions that prevail at various times, will not succeed very well, because each organism will fare well at one period of its life but not at others. A better strategy is to have a population with one or a few genotypes that survive well in all the successive environments. If the environment changes from place to place, the situation is likely to be different. Although a single genotype, well adapted to the various environmental patches, is a possible strategy, a variety of genotypes, with some individuals optimally adapted to each subenvironment, might fare still better. The ability of the population to exploit the environmental patchiness is thereby increased. Diversifying selection refers to the situation in which natural selection favours different genotypes in different subenvironments. The efficiency of diversifying natural selection is quite apparent in circumstances in which populations living a short distance apart have become genetically differentiated. In one example, populations of bent grass can be found growing on heaps of mining refuse heavily contaminated with metals such as lead and copper. The soil has become so contaminated that it is toxic to most plants, but the dense stands of bent grass growing over these refuse heaps have been shown to possess genes that make them resistant to high concentrations of lead and copper. But only a few metres from the contaminated soil can be found bent grass plants that are not resistant to these metals. Bent grasses reproduce primarily by cross-pollination, so that the resistant grass receives wind-borne pollen from the neighbouring nonresistant plants. Yet they maintain their genetic differentiation because nonresistant seedlings are unable to grow in the contaminated soil and, in nearby uncontaminated soil, the nonresistant seedlings outgrow the resistant ones. The evolution of these resistant strains has taken place in the fewer than 400 years since the mines were first opened. Protective morphologies and protective coloration exist in many animals as a defense against predators or as a cover against prey. Sometimes an organism mimics (mimicry) the appearance of a different one for protection. Diversifying selection often occurs in association with mimicry. A species of swallowtail butterfly, Papilio dardanus, is endemic in tropical and Southern Africa. Males have yellow and black wings, with characteristic tails in the second pair of wings. But females in many localities are conspicuously different from males; their wings lack tails and have colour patterns that vary from place to place. The explanation for these differences stems from the fact that P. dardanus can be eaten safely by birds. Many other butterfly species are noxious to birds, and so they are carefully avoided as food. In localities where P. dardanus coexists with noxious butterfly species, the P. dardanus females have evolved an appearance that mimics the noxious species. Birds confuse the mimics with their models and do not prey on them. In different localities the females mimic different species; in some areas two or even three different female forms exist, each mimicking different noxious species. Diversifying selection has resulted in different phenotypes of P. dardanus as a protection from bird predators. Sexual selection Mutual attraction between the sexes is an important factor in reproduction. The males and females of many animal species are similar in size and shape except for the sexual organs and secondary sexual characteristics such as the breasts of female mammals. There are, however, species in which the sexes exhibit striking dimorphism. Particularly in birds and mammals, the males are often larger and stronger, more brightly coloured, or endowed with conspicuous adornments. But bright colours make animals more visible to predators—the long plumage of male peacocks and birds of paradise and the enormous antlers of aged male deer are cumbersome loads in the best of cases. Darwin knew that natural selection could not be expected to favour the evolution of disadvantageous traits, and he was able to offer a solution to this problem. He proposed that such traits arise by “sexual selection,” which “depends not on a struggle for existence in relation to other organic beings or to external conditions but on a struggle between the individuals of one sex, generally the males, for the possession of the other sex.” The concept of sexual selection as a special form of natural selection is easily explained. Other things being equal, organisms more proficient in securing mates have higher fitness. There are two general circumstances leading to sexual selection. One is the preference shown by one sex (often the females) for individuals of the other sex that exhibit certain traits. The other is increased strength (usually among the males) that yields greater success in securing mates. The presence of a particular trait among the members of one sex can make them somehow more attractive to the opposite sex. This type of “sex appeal” has been experimentally demonstrated in all sorts of animals, from vinegar flies to pigeons, mice, dogs, and rhesus monkeys. When, for example, Drosophila flies, some with yellow bodies as a result of spontaneous mutation and others with the normal yellowish gray pigmentation, are placed together, normal males are preferred over yellow males by females with either body colour. Sexual selection can also come about because a trait—the antlers of a stag, for example—increases prowess in competition with members of the same sex. Stags, rams, and bulls use antlers or horns in contests of strength; a winning male usually secures more female mates. Therefore, sexual selection may lead to increased size and aggressiveness in males. Male baboons are more than twice as large as females, and the behaviour of the docile females contrasts with that of the aggressive males. A similar dimorphism occurs in the northern sea lion, Eumetopias jubata, where males weigh about 1,000 kg (2,200 pounds), about three times as much as females. The males fight fiercely in their competition for females; large, battle-scarred males occupy their own rocky islets, each holding a harem of as many as 20 females. Among many mammals that live in packs, troops, or herds—such as wolves, horses, and buffaloes—there usually is a hierarchy of dominance based on age and strength, with males that rank high in the hierarchy doing most of the mating. Kin selection and reciprocal altruism The apparent altruistic behaviour of many animals is, like some manifestations of sexual selection, a trait that at first seems incompatible with the theory of natural selection. Altruism is a form of behaviour that benefits other individuals at the expense of the one that performs the action; the fitness of the altruist is diminished by its behaviour, whereas individuals that act selfishly benefit from it at no cost to themselves. Accordingly, it might be expected that natural selection would foster the development of selfish behaviour and eliminate altruism. This conclusion is not so compelling when it is noticed that the beneficiaries of altruistic behaviour are usually relatives. They all carry the same genes, including the genes that promote altruistic behaviour. Altruism may evolve by kin selection, which is simply a type of natural selection in which relatives are taken into consideration when evaluating an individual's fitness. Natural selection favours genes that increase the reproductive success of their carriers, but it is not necessary that all individuals that share a given genotype have higher reproductive success. It suffices that carriers of the genotype reproduce more successfully on the average than those possessing alternative genotypes. A parent shares half of its genes with each progeny, so a gene that promotes parental altruism is favoured by selection if the behaviour's cost to the parent is less than half of its average benefits to the progeny. Such a gene will be more likely to increase in frequency through the generations than an alternative gene that does not promote altruistic behaviour. Parental care is, therefore, a form of altruism readily explained by kin selection. The parent spends some energy caring for the progeny because it increases the reproductive success of the parent's genes. Kin selection extends beyond the relationship between parents and their offspring. It facilitates the development of altruistic behaviour when the energy invested, or the risk incurred, by an individual is compensated in excess by the benefits ensuing to relatives. The closer the relationship between the beneficiaries and the altruist and the greater the number of beneficiaries, the higher the risks and efforts warranted in the altruist. Individuals that live together in a herd or troop usually are related and often behave toward each other in this way. Adult zebras, for instance, will turn toward an attacking predator to protect the young in the herd rather than fleeing to protect themselves. Altruism also occurs among unrelated individuals when the behaviour is reciprocal and the altruist's costs are smaller than the benefits to the recipient. This reciprocal altruism is found in the mutual grooming of chimpanzees and other primates as they clean each other of lice and other pests. Another example appears in flocks of birds that post sentinels to warn of danger. A crow sitting in a tree watching for predators while the rest of the flock forages incurs a small loss by not feeding, but this loss is well compensated by the protection it receives when it itself forages and others of the flock stand guard. A particularly valuable contribution of the theory of kin selection is its explanation of the evolution of social behaviour among ants, bees, wasps, and other social insects (social insect). In honeybee populations, for example, the female workers build the hive, care for the young, and gather food, but they are sterile; the queen bee alone produces progeny. It would seem that the workers' behaviour would in no way be promoted or maintained by natural selection. Any genes causing such behaviour would seem likely to be eliminated from the population, because individuals exhibiting the behaviour increase not their own reproductive success but that of the queen. The situation is, however, more complex. Queen bees produce some eggs that remain unfertilized and develop into males, or drones, having a mother but no father. Their main role is to engage in the nuptial flight during which one of them fertilizes a new queen. Other eggs laid by queen bees are fertilized and develop into females, the large majority of which are workers. A queen typically mates with a single male once during her lifetime; the male's sperm is stored in the queen's spermatheca, from which it is gradually released as she lays fertilized eggs. All the queen's female progeny therefore have the same father, so that workers are more closely related to one another and to any new sister queen than they are to the mother queen. The female workers receive one-half of their genes from the mother and one-half from the father, but they share among themselves three-quarters of their genes. The half of the set from the father is the same in every worker, because the father had only one set of genes rather than two to pass on (the male developed from an unfertilized egg, so all his sperm carry the same set of genes). The other half of the workers' genes come from the mother, and on the average half of them are identical in any two sisters. Consequently, with three-quarters of her genes present in her sisters but only half of her genes able to be passed on to a daughter, a worker's genes are transmitted one and a half times more effectively when she raises a sister (whether another worker or a new queen) than if she produces a daughter of her own. species and speciation The concept of species Darwin sought to explain the splendid multiformity of the living world—thousands of organisms of the most diverse kinds, from lowly worms to spectacular birds of paradise, from yeasts and molds to oaks and orchids. His On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection (1859) is a sustained argument showing that the diversity of organisms and their characteristics can be explained as the result of natural processes. species come about as the result of gradual change prompted by natural selection. Environments are continuously changing in time, and they differ from place to place. Natural selection therefore favours different characteristics in different situations. The accumulation of differences eventually yields different species. Everyday experience teaches that there are different kinds of organisms and also teaches how to identify them. Everyone knows that people belong to the human species and are different from cats and dogs, which in turn are different from each other. There are differences between people, as well as between cats and dogs, but individuals of the same species are considerably more similar among themselves than they are to individuals of other species. External similarity is the common basis for identifying individuals as being members of the same species. Nevertheless, there is more to a species than outward appearance. A bulldog, a terrier, and a golden retriever are very different in appearance, but they are all dogs because they can interbreed. People can also interbreed with one another, and so can cats with other cats, but people cannot interbreed with dogs or cats, nor can these with each other. It is clear then that, although species are usually identified by appearance, there is something basic, of great biological significance, behind similarity of appearance—individuals of a species are able to interbreed with one another but not with members of other species. This is expressed in the following definition: Species are groups of interbreeding natural populations that are reproductively isolated from other such groups. (For an explanation and discussion of this concept, see below Reproductive isolation (evolution).) The ability to interbreed is of great evolutionary importance, because it determines that species are independent evolutionary units. Genetic changes originate in single individuals; they can spread by natural selection to all members of the species but not to individuals of other species. Individuals of a species share a common gene pool that is not shared by individuals of other species. Different species have independently evolving gene pools because they are reproductively isolated. Although the criterion for deciding whether individuals belong to the same species is clear, there may be ambiguity in practice for two reasons. One is lack of knowledge—it may not be known for certain whether individuals living in different sites belong to the same species, because it is not known whether they can naturally interbreed. The other reason for ambiguity is rooted in the nature of evolution as a gradual process. Two geographically separate populations that at one time were members of the same species later may have diverged into two different species. Since the process is gradual, there is no particular point at which it is possible to say that the two populations have become two different species. A related situation pertains to organisms living at different times. There is no way to test if today's humans could interbreed with those who lived thousands of years ago. It seems reasonable that living people, or living cats, would be able to interbreed with people, or cats, exactly like those that lived a few generations earlier. But what about ancestors removed by a thousand or a million generations? The ancestors of modern humans that lived 500,000 years ago (about 20,000 generations) are classified as the species Homo erectus. There is no exact time at which H. erectus became H. sapiens (Homo sapiens), but it would not be appropriate to classify remote human ancestors and modern humans in the same species just because the changes from one generation to the next were small. It is useful to distinguish between the two groups by means of different species names, just as it is useful to give different names to childhood and adulthood even though no single moment can separate one from the other. Biologists distinguish species in organisms that lived at different times by means of a commonsense morphological (morphology) criterion: If two organisms differ from each other in form and structure about as much as do two living individuals belonging to two different species, they are classified in separate species and given different names. The definition of species given above applies only to organisms able to interbreed. Bacteria and cyanobacteria (blue-green algae), for example, reproduce not sexually but by fission. Organisms that lack sexual reproduction are classified into different species according to criteria such as external morphology, chemical and physiological properties, and genetic constitution. The origin of species Reproductive isolation Among sexual organisms, individuals that are able to interbreed belong to the same species. The biological properties of organisms that prevent interbreeding are called reproductive isolating mechanisms (RIMs). Oaks on different islands, minnows in different rivers, or squirrels in different mountain ranges cannot interbreed because they are physically separated, not necessarily because they are biologically incompatible. Geographic separation, therefore, is not a RIM. There are two general categories of reproductive isolating mechanisms: prezygotic, or those that take effect before fertilization, and postzygotic, those that take effect afterward. Prezygotic RIMs prevent the formation of hybrids between members of different populations through ecological, temporal, ethological (behavioral), mechanical, and gametic isolation. Postzygotic RIMs reduce the viability or fertility of hybrids or their progeny. Ecological isolation Populations may occupy the same territory but live in different habitats and so not meet. The Anopheles maculipennis group consists of six mosquito species, some of which are involved in the transmission of malaria. Although the species are virtually indistinguishable morphologically, they are isolated reproductively, in part because they breed in different habitats. Some breed in brackish water, others in running fresh water, and still others in stagnant fresh water. Temporal isolation Populations may mate or flower at different seasons or different times of day. Three tropical orchid species of the genus Dendrobium each flower for a single day; the flowers open at dawn and wither by nightfall. Flowering occurs in response to certain meteorological stimuli, such as a sudden storm on a hot day. The same stimulus acts on all three species, but the lapse between the stimulus and flowering is 8 days in one species, 9 in another, and 10 or 11 in the third. Interspecific fertilization is impossible because, at the time the flowers of one species open, those of the other species have already withered or have not yet matured. A peculiar form of temporal isolation exists between pairs of closely related species of cicadas, in which one species of each pair emerges every 13 years, the other every 17 years. The two species of a pair may be sympatric (live in the same territory), but they have an opportunity to form hybrids only once every 221 (or 13 × 17) years. Ethological (behavioral) isolation Sexual attraction between males and females of a given species may be weak or absent. In most animal species, members of the two sexes must first search for each other and come together. Complex courtship rituals then take place, with the male often taking the initiative and the female responding. This in turn generates additional actions by the male and responses by the female, and eventually there is copulation, or sexual intercourse (or, in the case of some aquatic organisms, release of the sex cells for fertilization in the water). These elaborate rituals are specific to a species and play a significant part in species recognition. If the sequence of events in the search-courting-mating process is rendered disharmonious by either of the two sexes, then the entire process will be interrupted. Courtship and mating rituals have been extensively analyzed in some mammals, birds, and fishes and in a number of insect species (see reproductive behaviour). Ethological isolation is often the most potent RIM to keep animal species from interbreeding. It can be remarkably strong even among closely related species. The vinegar flies Drosophila serrata, D. birchii, and D. dominicana are three sibling species (that is, species nearly indistinguishable morphologically) that are endemic in Australia and on the islands of New Guinea and New Britain. In many areas these three species occupy the same territory, but no hybrids are known to occur in nature. The strength of their ethological isolation has been tested in the laboratory by placing together groups of females and males in various combinations for several days. When the flies were all of the same species but the female and male groups each came from different geographic origins, a large majority of the females (usually 90 percent or more) were fertilized. But no inseminations or very few (less than 4 percent) took place when males and females were of different species, whether from the same or different geographic origins. It should be added that the rare interspecific inseminations that did occur among the vinegar flies produced hybrid adult individuals in very few instances, and the hybrids were always sterile. This illustrates a common pattern—reproductive isolation between species is maintained by several RIMs in succession; if one breaks down, others are still present. In addition to ethological isolation, failure of the hybrids to survive and hybrid sterility (see below Hybrid inviability (evolution) and Hybrid sterility (evolution)) prevent successful breeding between members of the three Drosophila species and between many other animal species as well. Species recognition during courtship involves stimuli that may be chemical (olfactory), visual, auditory, or tactile. pheromones are specific substances that play a critical role in recognition between members of a species; they have been chemically identified in such insects as ants, moths, butterflies, and beetles and in such vertebrates as fish, reptiles, and mammals. The “songs” of birds, frogs, and insects (the last of which produce these sounds by vibrating or rubbing their wings) are species recognition signals. Some form of physical contact or touching occurs in many mammals but also in Drosophila flies and other insects. Mechanical isolation Copulation (sexual intercourse) is often impossible between different animal species because of the incompatible shape and size of the genitalia. In plants, variations in flower structure may impede pollination. Two species of sage from California provide an example: The two-lipped flowers of Salvia mellifera have stamens and style (respectively, the male structure that produces the pollen and the female structure that bears the pollen-receptive surface, the stigma) in the upper lip, whereas S. apiana has long stamens and style and a specialized floral configuration. S. mellifera is pollinated by small or medium-sized bees that carry pollen on their backs from flower to flower. S. apiana, however, is pollinated by large carpenter bees and bumblebees that carry the pollen on their wings and other body parts. Even if the pollinators of one species visit flowers of the other, pollination cannot occur because the pollen does not come into contact with the style of the alternative species. Gametic isolation Marine animals often discharge their eggs and sperm into the surrounding water, where fertilization takes place. Gametes of different species may fail to attract one another. For example, the sea urchins Strongylocentrotus purpuratus and S. franciscanus can be induced to release their eggs and sperm simultaneously, but most of the fertilizations that result are between eggs and sperm of the same species. In animals with internal fertilization, sperm cells may be unable to function in the sexual ducts of females of different species. In plants, pollen grains of one species typically fail to germinate on the stigma of another species, so that the pollen tubes never reach the ovary where fertilization would occur. Hybrid inviability Occasionally, prezygotic mechanisms are absent or break down so that interspecific zygotes (fertilized eggs) are formed. These zygotes, however, often fail to develop into mature individuals. The hybrid embryos of sheep and goats, for example, die in the early developmental stages before birth. Hybrid inviability is common in plants, whose hybrid seeds often fail to germinate or die shortly after germination. Hybrid sterility Hybrid zygotes sometimes develop into adults, such as mules (hybrids between female horses and male donkeys), but the adults fail to develop functional gametes and are sterile. Hybrid breakdown In plants more than in animals, hybrids between closely related species are sometimes partially fertile. Gene exchange may nevertheless be inhibited because the offspring are poorly viable or sterile. Hybrids between the cotton species Gossypium barbadense, G. hirsutum, and G. tomentosum appear vigorous and fertile, but their progenies die in seed or early in development, or they develop into sparse, weak plants. A model of speciation Because species are groups of populations reproductively isolated from one another, asking about the origin of species is equivalent to asking how reproductive isolation arises between populations. Two theories have been advanced to answer this question. One theory considers isolation as an accidental by-product of genetic divergence. Populations that become genetically less and less alike (as a consequence, for example, of adaptation to different environments) may eventually be unable to interbreed because their gene pools are disharmonious. The other theory regards isolation as a product of natural selection. Whenever hybrid individuals are less fit than nonhybrids, natural selection will directly promote the development of RIMs. This occurs because genetic variants interfering with hybridization have greater fitness than those favouring hybridization, given that the latter are often present in hybrids with poor fitness. These two theories of the origin of reproductive isolation are not mutually exclusive. Reproductive isolation may indeed come about incidentally to genetic divergence between separated populations. Consider, for example, the evolution of many endemic species of plants and animals in the Hawaiian (Hawaii) archipelago. The ancestors of these species arrived on these islands several million years ago. There they evolved as they became adapted to the environmental conditions and colonizing opportunities present. Reproductive isolation between the populations evolving in Hawaii and the populations on continents was never directly promoted by natural selection because their geographic remoteness forestalled any opportunities for hybridizing. Nevertheless, reproductive isolation became complete in many cases as a result of gradual genetic divergence over thousands of generations. Frequently, however, the course of speciation involves the processes postulated by both theories—reproductive isolation starts as a by-product of gradual evolutionary divergence but is completed by natural selection directly promoting the evolution of prezygotic RIMs. The separate sets of processes identified by the two speciation theories may be seen, therefore, as different stages in the splitting of an evolutionary lineage into two species. The splitting starts when gene flow is somehow interrupted between two populations. It is necessary that gene flow be interrupted, because otherwise the two groups of individuals would still share in a common gene pool and fail to become genetically different. Interruption may be due to geographic separation, or it may be initiated by some genetic change that affects some individuals of the species but not others living in the same territory. The two genetically isolated groups are likely to become more and more different as time goes on. Eventually, some incipient reproductive isolation may take effect because the two gene pools are no longer adapting in concert. Hybrid individuals, which carry genes combined from the two gene pools, will therefore experience reduced viability or fertility. The circumstances just described may persist for so long that the populations become completely differentiated into separate species. It happens quite commonly, however, in both animals and plants that opportunities for hybridization arise between two populations that are becoming genetically differentiated. Two outcomes are possible. One is that the hybrids manifest little or no reduction of fitness, so that gene exchange between the two populations proceeds freely, eventually leading to their integration into a single gene pool. The second possible outcome is that reduction of fitness in the hybrids is sufficiently large for natural selection to favour the emergence of prezygotic RIMs preventing the formation of hybrids altogether. This situation may be identified as the second stage in the speciation process. How natural selection brings about the evolution of prezygotic RIMs can be understood in the following way. Beginning with two populations, P1 and P2, assume that there are gene variants in P1 that increase the probability that P1 individuals will choose P1 rather than P2 mates. Such gene variants will increase in frequency in the P1 population, because they are more often present in the progenies of P1 × P1 matings, which have normal fitness. The alternative genetic variants that do not favour P1 × P1 matings will be more often present in the progenies of P1 × P2 matings, which have lower fitness. The same process will enhance the frequency in the P2 population of genetic variants that lead P2 individuals to choose P2 rather than P1 mates. Prezygotic RIMs may therefore evolve in both populations and lead to their becoming two separate species. The two stages of the process of speciation can be characterized, finally, by outlining their distinctions. The first stage primarily involves the appearance of postzygotic RIMs as accidental by-products of overall genetic differentiation rather than as express targets of natural selection. The second stage involves the evolution of prezygotic RIMs that are directly promoted by natural selection. The first stage may come about suddenly, in one or a few generations, rather than as a long, gradual process. The second stage follows the first in time but need not always be present. Geographic speciation One common mode of speciation is known as geographic, or allopatric (in separate territories), speciation. The general model of the speciation process advanced in the previous section applies well to geographic speciation. The first stage begins as a result of geographic separation between populations. This may occur when a few colonizers reach a geographically separate habitat, perhaps an island, lake, river, isolated valley, or mountain range. Alternately, a population may be split into two geographically separate ones by topographic changes, such as the disappearance of a water connection between two lakes, or by an invasion of competitors, parasites, or predators into the intermediate zone. If these types of geographic separation continue for some time, postzygotic RIMs may appear as a result of gradual genetic divergence. In the second stage, an opportunity for interbreeding may later be brought about by topographic changes reestablishing continuity between the previously isolated territories or by ecological changes once again making the intermediate territory habitable for the organisms. If postzygotic RIMs that evolved during the separation period sufficiently reduce the fitness of hybrids of the two populations, natural selection will foster the development of prezygotic RIMs, and the two populations may go on to evolve into two species despite their occupying the same geographic territory. Investigation has been made of many populations that are in the first stage of geographic speciation. There are fewer well-documented instances of the second stage, presumably because this occurs fairly rapidly in evolutionary time. Both stages of speciation are present in a group of six closely related species of New World Drosophila flies that have been extensively studied by evolutionists for several decades. Two of these sibling species, D. willistoni and D. equinoxialis, each consist of groups of populations in the first stage of speciation and are identified as different subspecies. Two D. willistoni subspecies live in continental South America—D. willistoni quechua lives west of the Andes and D. willistoni willistoni east of the Andes. They are effectively separated by the Andes because the flies cannot live at high altitudes. It is not known whether their geographic separation is as old as the Andes, but it has existed long enough for postzygotic RIMs to have evolved. When the two subspecies are crossed in the laboratory, the hybrid males are completely sterile if the mother came from the quechua subspecies, but in the reciprocal cross all hybrids are fertile. If hybridization should occur in nature, selection would favour the evolution of prezygotic RIMs because of the complete sterility of half of the hybrid males. Another pair of subspecies consists of D. equinoxialis equinoxialis, which inhabits continental South America, and D. equinoxialis caribbensis, which lives in Central America and the Caribbean. Crosses made in the laboratory between these two subspecies always produce sterile males, irrespective of the subspecies of the mother. Natural selection would, then, promote prezygotic RIMs between these two subspecies more strongly than between those of D. willistoni. But, in accord with the speciation model presented above, laboratory experiments show no evidence of the development of ethological isolation or of any other prezygotic RIM, presumably because the geographic isolation of the subspecies has forestalled hybridization between members. One more sibling species of the group is D. paulistorum, a species that includes groups of populations well into the second stage of geographic speciation. Six such groups have been identified as semispecies, or incipient species, two or three of which are sympatric in many localities. Male hybrids between individuals of the different semispecies are sterile; laboratory crosses always yield fertile females but sterile males. Whenever two or three incipient species of D. paulistorum have come into contact in nature, the second stage of speciation has led to the development of ethological isolation, which ranges from incipient to virtually complete. Laboratory experiments show that, when both incipient species are from the same locality, their ethological isolation is complete; only individuals of the same incipient species mate. When the individuals from different incipient species come from different localities, however, ethological isolation is usually present but far from complete. This is precisely as the speciation model predicts. Natural selection effectively promotes ethological isolation in territories where two incipient species live together, but the genes responsible for this isolation have not yet fully spread to populations in which one of the two incipient species is not present. The eventual outcome of the process of geographic speciation is complete reproductive isolation, as can be observed among the species of the New World Drosophila group under discussion. D. willistoni, D. equinoxialis, D. tropicalis, and D. paulistorum coexist sympatrically over wide regions of Central and South America while preserving their separate gene pools. Hybrids are not known in nature and are almost impossible to obtain in the laboratory; moreover, all interspecific hybrid males at least are completely sterile. This total reproductive isolation has evolved, however, with very little morphological differentiation. Females from different sibling species cannot be distinguished by experts, while males can be identified only by small differences in the shape of their genitalia, unrecognizable except under a microscope. adaptive radiation The geographic separation of populations derived from common ancestors may continue long enough so that the populations become completely differentiated species before ever regaining sympatry and the opportunity to interbreed. As the allopatric populations continue evolving independently, RIMs develop and morphological differences may arise. The second stage of speciation—in which natural selection directly stimulates the evolution of RIMs—never comes about in such situations, because reproductive isolation takes place simply as a consequence of the continued separate evolution of the populations. This form of allopatric speciation is particularly apparent when colonizers reach geographically remote areas, such as islands, where they find few or no competitors and have an opportunity to diverge as they become adapted to the new environment. Sometimes the new regions offer a multiplicity of environments to the colonizers, giving rise to several different lineages and species. This process of rapid divergence of multiple species from a single ancestral lineage is called adaptive radiation. Many examples of speciation by adaptive radiation are found in archipelagoes removed from the mainland. The Galapagos Islands are about 1,000 km (600 miles) off the west coast of South America. When Charles Darwin (Darwin, Charles) arrived there in 1835 during his voyage on the HMS Beagle, he discovered many species not found anywhere else in the world—for example, several species of finches, of which 14 are now known to exist (Galapagos finch) (called Galapagos (Galapagos finch), or Darwin's, finches). These passerine birds have adapted to a diversity of habitats and diets, some feeding mostly on plants, others exclusively on insects. The various shapes of their bills are clearly adapted to probing, grasping, biting, or crushing—the diverse ways in which the different Galapagos species obtain their food. The explanation for such diversity is that the ancestor of Galapagos finches arrived in the islands before other kinds of birds and encountered an abundance of unoccupied ecological niches. Its descendants underwent adaptive radiation, evolving a variety of finch species with ways of life capable of exploiting opportunities that on various continents are already exploited by other species. The Hawaiian archipelago also provides striking examples of adaptive radiation. Its several volcanic islands, ranging from about 1 million to more than 10 million years in age, are far from any continent or even other large islands. In their relatively small total land area, an astounding number of plant and animal species exist. Most of the species have evolved on the islands, among them about two dozen species (about one-third of them now extinct) of honeycreeper (Hawaiian honeycreeper)s, birds of the family Drepanididae (Hawaiian honeycreeper), all derived from a single immigrant form. In fact, all but one of Hawaii's 71 native bird species are endemic; that is, they have evolved there and are found nowhere else. More than 90 percent of the native species of flowering plants, land mollusks, and insects are also endemic, as are two-thirds of the 168 species of ferns. There are more than 500 native Hawaiian species of Drosophila flies—about one-third of the world's total number of known species. Far greater morphological and ecological diversity exists among the species in Hawaii than anywhere else in the world. The species of Drosophila in Hawaii have diverged by adaptive radiation from one or a few colonizers, which encountered an assortment of ecological niches that in other lands were occupied by different groups of flies or insects but that were available for exploitation in these remote islands. Quantum speciation In some modes of speciation the first stage is achieved in a short period of time. These modes are known by a variety of names, such as quantum, rapid, and saltational speciation, all suggesting the shortening of time involved. They are also known as sympatric speciation, alluding to the fact that quantum speciation often leads to speciation between populations that exist in the same territory or habitat. An important form of quantum speciation, polyploidy (evolution), is discussed separately below. Quantum speciation without polyploidy has been seen in the annual plant genus Clarkia. Two closely related species, Clarkia biloba and C. lingulata, are both native to California. C. lingulata is known only from two sites in the central Sierra Nevada at the southern periphery of the distribution of C. biloba, from which it evolved starting with translocations and other chromosomal mutations (see above Chromosomal mutations (evolution)). Such chromosomal rearrangements arise suddenly but reduce the fertility of heterozygous individuals. Clarkia species are capable of self-fertilization, which facilitates the propagation of the chromosomal mutants in different sets of individuals even within a single locality. This makes hybridization possible with nonmutant individuals and allows the second stage of speciation to go ahead. Chromosomal mutations are often the starting point of quantum speciation in animals, particularly in groups such as moles and other rodents that live underground or have little mobility. Mole rats of the species group Spalax ehrenbergi in Israel and gophers of the species group Thomomys talpoides in the northern Rocky Mountains are well-studied examples. The speciation process may also be initiated by changes in just one or a few gene loci when these alterations result in a change of ecological niche or, in the case of parasites (parasitism), a change of host. Many parasites use their host as a place for courtship and mating, so organisms with two different host preferences may become reproductively isolated. If the hybrids show poor fitness because they are not effective parasites in either of the two hosts, natural selection will favour the development of additional RIMs. This type of speciation seems to be common among parasitic insects, a large group comprising tens of thousands of species. polyploidy As discussed above in Chromosomal mutations (evolution), the multiplication of entire sets of chromosomes is known as polyploidy. Whereas a diploid organism carries in the nucleus of each cell two sets of chromosomes, one inherited from each parent, a polyploid organism has three or more sets of chromosomes. Many cultivated plants are polyploid—bananas are triploid, potatoes are tetraploid, bread wheat is hexaploid, some strawberries are octaploid. These cultivated polyploids do not exist in nature, at least in any significant frequency. Some of them first appeared spontaneously; others, such as octaploid strawberries, were intentionally produced. In animals polyploidy is relatively rare because it disrupts the balance between the sex chromosome and the other chromosomes, a balance being required for the proper development of sex. Naturally polyploid species are found in hermaphroditic animals—individuals having both male and female organs—which include snails, earthworms, and planarians (a group of flatworms). They are also found in forms with parthenogenetic (parthenogenesis) females (which produce viable progeny without fertilization), such as some beetles, sow bugs, goldfish, and salamanders. All major groups of plants have naturally polyploid species, but they are most common among angiosperms, or flowering plants, of which about 47 percent are polyploids. Polyploidy is rare among gymnosperms, such as pines, firs, and cedars, although the redwood, Sequoia sempervirens, is a polyploid. Most polyploid plants are tetraploids. Polyploids with three, five, or some other odd-number multiple of the basic chromosome number are sterile, because the separation of homologous chromosomes cannot be achieved properly during formation of the sex cells. Some plants with an odd number of chromosome sets persist by means of asexual reproduction, particularly through human cultivation; the triploid banana is one example. Polyploidy is a mode of quantum speciation that yields the beginnings of a new species in just one or two generations. There are two kinds of polyploids—autopolyploids, which derive from a single species, and allopolyploids, which stem from a combination of chromosome sets from different species. Allopolyploid plant species are much more numerous than autopolyploids. An allopolyploid species can originate from two plant species that have the same diploid number of chromosomes. The chromosome complement of one species may be symbolized as AA and the other BB. A hybrid of two different species, represented as AB, will usually be sterile because of abnormal chromosome pairing and segregation during formation at meiosis of the gametes, which are haploid (i.e., having only half of the chromosomes, of which in a given gamete some come from the A set and some from the B set). But chromosome doubling may occur in a diploid cell as a consequence of abnormal mitosis, in which the chromosomes divide but the cell does not. If this happens in the hybrid above, AB, the result is a plant cell with four sets of chromosomes, AABB. Such a tetraploid cell may proliferate within the plant (which is otherwise constituted of diploid cells) and produce branches and flowers of tetraploid cells. Because the flowers' cells carry two chromosomes of each kind, they can produce functional diploid gametes via meiosis with the constitution AB. The union of two such gametes, such as happens during self-fertilization, produces a complete tetraploid individual (AABB). In this way, self-fertilization in plants makes possible the formation of a tetraploid individual as the result of a single abnormal cell division. Autopolyploids originate in a similar fashion, except that the individual in which the abnormal mitosis occurs is not a hybrid. Self-fertilization thus enables a single individual to multiply and give rise to a population. This population is a new species, since polyploid individuals are reproductively isolated from their diploid ancestors. A cross between a tetraploid and a diploid yields triploid progeny, which are sterile. Genetic differentiation during speciation Genetic changes underlie all evolutionary processes. In order to understand speciation and its role in evolution, it is useful to know how much genetic change takes place during the course of species development. It is of considerable significance to ascertain whether new species arise by altering only a few genes or whether the process requires drastic changes—a genetic “revolution,” as postulated by some evolutionists in the past. The issue is best considered separately with respect to each of the two stages of speciation and to the various modes of speciation. The question of how much genetic differentiation occurs during speciation has become answerable only with the relatively recent development of appropriate methods for comparing genes of different species. Genetic change is measured with two parameters—genetic identity (I), which estimates the proportion of genes that are identical in two populations, and genetic distance (D), which estimates the proportion of gene changes that have occurred in the separate evolution of two populations. The value of I may range between 0 and 1, which correspond to the extreme situations in which no or all genes are identical, respectively; the value of D may range from zero to infinity. D can reach beyond 1 because each gene may change more than once in one or both populations as evolution goes on for many generations. As a model of geographic speciation, the Drosophila willistoni group of flies offers the distinct advantage of exhibiting both stages of the speciation process. The D. willistoni group consists of several closely related species, some of which in turn consist of several incipient species, subspecies, or both. About 30 randomly selected genes have been studied in a large number of natural populations of these species. The results are summarized in the figure-->. The most significant numbers are those given in the levels of comparison labeled 2 and 3, which represent the first and second stages, respectively, of the process of geographic speciation. The 0.230 value for D (figure, level 2) means that about 23 gene changes have occurred for every 100 gene loci in the separate evolution of two subspecies—that is, the sum of the changes that have occurred in the two separately evolving lineages is 23 percent of all the genes. These are populations well advanced in the first stage of speciation, as manifested by the sterility of the hybrid males. The genetic distance between incipient species (figure, level 3) is the same, within experimental error, as that between the subspecies, or 22.6 percent. This implies that the development of ethological isolation, as it is found in these populations, does not require many genetic changes beyond those that occurred during the first stage of speciation. Indeed, no additional gene changes were detected in these experiments. The absence of major genetic changes during the second stage of speciation can be understood by considering the role of natural selection, which directly promotes the evolution of prezygotic RIMs during the second stage, so that only genes modifying mate choice need to change. In contrast, the development of postzygotic RIMs during the first stage occurs only after there is substantial genetic differentiation between populations, because it comes about only as an incidental outcome of overall genetic divergence. Sibling species, such as D. willistoni and D. equinoxialis, exhibit 58 gene changes for every 100 gene loci after their divergence from a common ancestor (figure, level 4). It is noteworthy that this much genetic evolution has occurred without altering the external morphology of these organisms. In the evolution of morphologically different species (figure, level 5), the number of gene changes is greater yet, as would be expected. Genetic changes concomitant with one or the other of the two stages in the speciation process have been studied in a number of organisms, from insects and other invertebrates to all sorts of vertebrates, including mammals. The amount of genetic change during geographic speciation varies between organisms, but the two main observations made in the D. willistoni group seem to apply quite generally. These are that the evolution of postzygotic mechanisms during the first stage is accompanied by substantial genetic change (a majority of values for genetic distance, D, range between 0.15 and 0.30) and that relatively few additional genetic changes are required during the second stage. The conclusions drawn from the investigation of geographic speciation make it possible to predict the relative amounts of genetic change expected in the quantum modes of speciation. Polyploid species are a special case—they arise suddenly in one or a few generations, and at first they are not expected to be genetically different from their ancestors. More generally, quantum speciation involves a shortening of the first stage of speciation, so that postzygotic RIMs arise directly as a consequence of specific genetic changes (such as chromosome mutations). Populations in the first stage of quantum speciation, therefore, need not be substantially different in individual gene loci. This has been confirmed by genetic investigations of species recently arisen by quantum speciation. For example, the average genetic distance between four incipient species of the mole rat Spalax ehrenbergi is 0.022, and between those of the gopher Thomomys talpoides it is 0.078. The second stage of speciation is modulated in essentially the same way as in the geographic mode. Not many gene changes are needed in either case to complete speciation. Patterns and rates of species evolution Evolution within a lineage and by lineage splitting Evolution can take place by anagenesis, in which changes occur within a lineage, or by cladogenesis, in which a lineage splits into two or more separate lines. Anagenetic evolution has doubled the size of the human cranium over the course of two million years; in the lineage of the horse it has reduced the number of toes from four to one. Cladogenetic evolution has produced the extraordinary diversity of the living world, with its more than two million species of animals, plants, fungi, and microorganisms. The most essential cladogenetic function is speciation, the process by which one species splits into two or more species. Because species are reproductively isolated from one another, they are independent evolutionary units; that is, evolutionary changes occurring in one species are not shared with other species. Over time, species diverge more and more from one another as a consequence of anagenetic evolution. Descendant lineages of two related species that existed millions of years ago may now be classified into quite different biological categories, such as different genera or even different families. The evolution of all living organisms, or of a subset of them, can be seen as a tree, with branches that divide into two or more as time progresses. Such trees are called phylogenies (phylogeny). Their branches represent evolving lineages, some of which eventually die out while others persist in themselves or in their derived lineages down to the present time. Evolutionists are interested in the history of life and hence in the topology, or configuration, of phylogenies. They are concerned as well with the nature of the anagenetic changes within lineages and with the timing of the events. Phylogenetic relationships are ascertained by means of several complementary sources of evidence. First, there are the discovered remnants of organisms that lived in the past, the fossil record, which provides definitive evidence of relationships between some groups of organisms. The fossil record, however, is far from complete and is often seriously deficient. Second, information about phylogeny comes from comparative studies of living forms. comparative anatomy contributed the most information in the past, although additional knowledge came from comparative embryology, cytology, ethology, biogeography, and other biological disciplines. In recent years the comparative study of the so-called informational macromolecules— proteins and nucleic acids, whose specific sequences of constituents carry genetic information—has become a powerful tool for the study of phylogeny (see below DNA and protein as informational macromolecules (evolution)). Morphological similarities between organisms have probably always been recognized. In ancient Greece Aristotle and later his followers and those of Plato, particularly Porphyry, classified (taxonomy) organisms (as well as inanimate objects) on the basis of similarities. The Aristotelian system of classification was further developed by some medieval Scholastic philosophers, notably Albertus Magnus (Albertus Magnus, Saint) and Thomas Aquinas (Aquinas, Thomas, Saint). The modern foundations of biological taxonomy, the science of classification of living and extinct organisms, were laid in the 18th century by the Swedish botanist Carolus Linnaeus (Linnaeus, Carolus) and the French botanist Michel Adanson (Adanson, Michel). The French naturalist Lamarck (Lamarck, Jean-Baptiste) dedicated much of his work to the systematic classification of organisms. He proposed that their similarities were due to ancestral relationships—in other words, to the degree of evolutionary proximity. The modern theory of evolution provides a causal explanation of the similarities between living things. Organisms evolve by a process of descent with modification. Changes, and therefore differences, gradually accumulate over the generations. The more recent the last common ancestor of a group of organisms, the less their differentiation; similarities of form and function reflect phylogenetic propinquity. Accordingly, phylogenetic affinities can be inferred on the basis of relative similarity. Convergent and parallel evolution A distinction has to be made between resemblances due to propinquity of descent and those due only to similarity of function. As discussed above in the section The evidence for evolution: Structural similarities (evolution), correspondence of features in different organisms that is due to inheritance from a common ancestor is called homology. The forelimbs of humans, whales, dogs, and bats are homologous. The skeletons of these limbs are all constructed of bones arranged according to the same pattern because they derive from a common ancestor with similarly arranged forelimbs. Correspondence of features due to similarity of function but not related to common descent is termed analogy. The wings of birds and of flies are analogous. Their wings are not modified versions of a structure present in a common ancestor but rather have developed independently as adaptations to a common function, flying. The similarities between the wings of bats and birds are partially homologous and partially analogous. Their skeletal structure is homologous, due to common descent from the forelimb of a reptilian ancestor; but the modifications for flying are different and independently evolved, and in this respect they are analogous. Features that become more rather than less similar through independent evolution are said to be convergent. Convergence is often associated with similarity of function, as in the evolution of wings in birds, bats, and flies. The shark (a fish) and the dolphin (a mammal) are much alike in external morphology; their similarities are due to convergence, since they have evolved independently as adaptations to aquatic life. Taxonomists also speak of parallel evolution. Parallelism and convergence are not always clearly distinguishable. Strictly speaking, convergent evolution occurs when descendants resemble each other more than their ancestors did with respect to some feature. Parallel evolution implies that two or more lineages have changed in similar ways, so that the evolved descendants are as similar to each other as their ancestors were. The evolution of marsupials in Australia, for example, paralleled the evolution of placental mammals in other parts of the world. There are Australian marsupials resembling true wolves, cats, mice, squirrels, moles, groundhogs, and anteaters. These placental mammals and the corresponding Australian marsupials evolved independently but in parallel lines by reason of their adaptation to similar ways of life. Some resemblances between a true anteater (genus Myrmecophaga) and a marsupial anteater, or numbat (Myrmecobius), are due to homology—both are mammals. Others are due to analogy—both feed on ants. Parallel and convergent evolution are also common in plants. New World cacti (cactus) and African euphorbias, or spurges, are alike in overall appearance although they belong to separate families. Both are succulent, spiny, water-storing plants adapted to the arid conditions of the desert. Their corresponding morphologies have evolved independently in response to similar environmental challenges. Homology can be recognized not only between different organisms but also between repetitive structures of the same organism. This has been called serial homology. There is serial homology, for example, between the arms and legs of humans, between the seven cervical vertebrae of mammals, and between the branches or leaves of a tree. The jointed appendages of arthropods are elaborate examples of serial homology. crayfish have 19 pairs of appendages, all built according to the same basic pattern but serving diverse functions—sensing, chewing, food handling, walking, mating, egg carrying, and swimming. Although serial homologies are not useful in reconstructing the phylogenetic relationships of organisms, they are an important dimension of the evolutionary process. Relationships in some sense akin to those between serial homologs exist at the molecular level between genes and proteins derived from ancestral gene duplications. The genes coding for the various hemoglobin chains are an example. About 500 million years ago a chromosome segment carrying the gene coding for hemoglobin became duplicated, so that the genes in the different segments thereafter evolved in somewhat different ways, one eventually giving rise to the modern gene coding for the α hemoglobin chain, the other for the β chain. The β chain gene became duplicated again about 200 million years ago, giving rise to the γ hemoglobin chain, a normal component of fetal hemoglobin (hemoblobin F). The genes for the α, β, γ, and other hemoglobin chains are homologous; similarities in their nucleotide sequences occur because they are modified descendants of a single ancestral sequence. There are two ways of comparing homology between hemoglobins. One is to compare the same hemoglobin chain—for instance, the α chain—in different species of animals. The degree of divergence between the α chains reflects the degree of the evolutionary relationship between the organisms, because the hemoglobin chains have evolved independently of one another since the time of divergence of the lineages leading to the present-day organisms. A second way is to make comparisons between, say, the α and β chains of a single species. The degree of divergence between the different globin chains reflects the degree of relationship between the genes coding for them. The different globins have evolved independently of each other since the time of duplication of their ancestral genes. Comparisons between homologous genes or proteins within a given organism provide information about the phylogenetic history of the genes and hence about the historical sequence of the gene duplication events. Whether similar features in different organisms are homologous or analogous—or simply accidental—cannot always be decided unambiguously, but the distinction must be made in order to determine phylogenetic relationships. Moreover, the degrees of homology must be quantified in some way so as to determine the propinquity of common descent between species. Difficulties arise here as well. In the case of forelimbs, it is not clear whether the homologies are greater between human and bird than between human and reptile, or between human and reptile than between human and bat. The fossil record sometimes provides the appropriate information, even though the record is deficient. Fossil evidence must be examined together with the evidence from comparative studies of living forms and with the quantitative estimates provided by comparative studies of proteins and nucleic acids. Gradual and punctuational evolution The fossil record indicates that morphological evolution is by and large a gradual process. Major evolutionary changes are usually due to a building-up over the ages of relatively small changes. But the fossil record is discontinuous. Fossil strata are separated by sharp boundaries; accumulation of fossils within a geologic deposit (stratum) is fairly constant over time, but the transition from one stratum to another may involve gaps of tens of thousands of years. Whereas the fossils within a stratum exhibit little morphological variation, new species—characterized by small but discontinuous morphological changes—typically appear at the boundaries between strata. That is not to say that the transition from one stratum to another always involves sudden changes in morphology; on the contrary, fossil forms often persist virtually unchanged through several geologic strata, each representing millions of years. The apparent morphological discontinuities of the fossil record are often attributed by paleontologists to the discontinuity of the sediments—that is, to the substantial time gaps encompassed in the boundaries between strata. The assumption is that, if the fossil deposits were more continuous, they would show a more gradual transition of form. Even so, morphological evolution would not always keep progressing gradually, because some forms, at least, remain unchanged for extremely long times. Examples are the lineages known as “living fossils”—for instance, the lamp shell (lamp shells) Lingula, a genus of brachiopod (a phylum of shelled invertebrates) that appears to have remained essentially unchanged since the Ordovician Period, some 450 million years ago; or the tuatara (Sphenodon punctatus), a reptile that has shown little morphological evolution for nearly 200 million years, since the early Mesozoic. Some paleontologists have proposed that the discontinuities of the fossil record are not artifacts created by gaps in the record but rather reflect the true nature of morphological evolution, which happens in sudden bursts associated with the formation of new species. The lack of morphological evolution, or stasis, of lineages such as Lingula and Sphenodon is in turn due to lack of speciation within those lineages. The proposition that morphological evolution is jerky, with most morphological change occurring during the brief speciation events and virtually no change during the subsequent existence of the species, is known as the punctuated equilibrium model. Whether morphological evolution in the fossil record is predominantly punctuational or gradual is a much-debated question. The imperfection of the record makes it unlikely that the issue will be settled in the foreseeable future. Intensive study of a favourable and abundant set of fossils may be expected to substantiate punctuated or gradual evolution in particular cases. But the argument is not about whether only one or the other pattern ever occurs; it is about their relative frequency. Some paleontologists argue that morphological evolution is in most cases gradual and only rarely jerky, whereas others think the opposite is true. Much of the problem is that gradualness or jerkiness is in the eye of the beholder. Consider the evolution of shell rib strength (the ratio of rib height to rib width) within a lineage of fossil brachiopods of the genus Eocelia. Results of the analysis of an abundant sample of fossils in Wales from near the beginning of the Devonian Period is shown in the figure-->. One possible interpretation of the data is that rib strength changed little or not at all from 415 million to 413 million years ago; rapid change ensued for the next 1 million years, followed by virtual stasis from 412 million to 407 million years ago; and then another short burst of change occurred about 406 million years ago, followed by a final period of stasis. On the other hand, the same record may be interpreted as not particularly punctuated but rather a gradual process, with the rate of change somewhat greater at particular times. The proponents of the punctuated equilibrium model propose not only that morphological evolution is jerky but also that it is associated with speciation events. They argue that phyletic evolution—that is, evolution along lineages of descent—proceeds at two levels. First, there is continuous change through time within a population. This consists largely of gene substitutions prompted by natural selection, mutation, genetic drift, and other genetic processes that operate at the level of the individual organism. The punctualists maintain that this continuous evolution within established lineages rarely, if ever, yields substantial morphological changes in species. Second, they say, there is the process of origination and extinction of species, in which most morphological change occurs. According to the punctualist model, evolutionary trends result from the patterns of origination and extinction of species rather than from evolution within established lineages. As discussed above in the section The origin of species (evolution), speciation involves the development of reproductive isolation between populations previously able to interbreed. Paleontologists discriminate between species by their different morphologies as preserved in the fossil record, but fossils cannot provide evidence of the development of reproductive isolation—new species that are reproductively isolated from their ancestors are often morphologically indistinguishable from them. Speciation as it is seen by paleontologists always involves substantial morphological change. This situation creates an insuperable difficulty for resolving the question of whether morphological evolution is always associated with speciation events. If speciation is defined as the evolution of reproductive isolation, the fossil record provides no evidence that an association between speciation and morphological change is necessary. But if new species are identified in the fossil record by morphological changes, then all such changes will occur concomitantly with the origination of new species. Diversity and extinction The current diversity of life is the balance between the species that have arisen through time and those that have become extinct. Paleontologists observe that organisms have continuously changed since the Cambrian Period, more than 500 million years ago, from which abundant animal fossil remains are known. The division of geologic history into a succession of eras and periods (see figure-->) is hallmarked by major changes in plant and animal life—the appearance of new sorts of organisms and the extinction of others. Paleontologists distinguish between background extinction, the steady rate at which species disappear through geologic time, and mass extinctions, the episodic events in which large numbers of species become extinct over time spans short enough to appear almost instantaneous on the geologic scale. Best known among mass extinctions is the one that occurred at the end of the Cretaceous Period, when the dinosaurs and many other marine and land animals disappeared. Most scientists believe that the Cretaceous mass extinction was provoked by the impact of an asteroid or comet on the tip of the Yucatán Peninsula in southeastern Mexico 65 million years ago. The object's impact caused an enormous dust cloud, which greatly reduced the Sun's radiation reaching Earth, with a consequent drastic drop in temperature and other adverse conditions. Among animals, about 76 percent of species, 47 percent of genera, and 16 percent of families became extinct. Although the dinosaurs vanished, turtles, snakes, lizards, crocodiles, and other reptiles, as well as some mammals and birds, survived. mammals that lived prior to the event were small and mostly nocturnal, but during the ensuing Tertiary Period they experienced an explosive diversification in size and morphology, occupying ecological niches vacated by the dinosaurs. Most of the orders and families of mammals now in existence originated in the first 10 million–20 million years after the dinosaurs' extinction. birds also greatly diversified at that time. Several other mass extinctions have occurred since the Cambrian. The most catastrophic happened at the end of the Permian Period, about 248 million years ago, when 95 percent of species, 82 percent of genera, and 51 percent of families of animals became extinct. (See also Triassic Period: Permian-Triassic extinctions (Triassic Period).) Other large mass extinctions occurred at or near the end of the Ordovician (Ordovician Period) (about 440 million years ago, 85 percent of species extinct), Devonian (Devonian Period) (about 360 million years ago, 83 percent of species extinct), and Triassic (Triassic Period) (about 210 million years ago, 80 percent of species extinct). Changes of climate and chemical composition of the atmosphere appear to have caused these mass extinctions; there is no convincing evidence that they resulted from cosmic impacts. Like other mass extinctions, they were followed by the origin or rapid diversification of various kinds of organisms. The first mammals and dinosaurs appeared after the late Permian extinction, and the first vascular plants after the Late Ordovician extinction. Background extinctions result from ordinary biological processes, such as competition between species, predation, and parasitism. When two species compete for very similar resources—say, the same kinds of seeds or fruits—one may become extinct, although often they will displace one another by dividing the territory or by specializing in slightly different foods, such as seeds of a different size or kind. Ordinary physical and climatic changes also account for background extinctions—for example, when a lake dries out or a mountain range rises or erodes. New species come about by the processes discussed in previous sections. These processes are largely gradual, yet the history of life shows major transitions in which one kind of organism becomes a very different kind. The earliest organisms were prokaryotes, or bacteria- (bacteria)like cells, whose hereditary material is not segregated into a nucleus. eukaryotes have their DNA organized into chromosomes that are membrane-bound in the nucleus, have other organelles inside their cells, and reproduce sexually. Eventually, eukaryotic multicellular organisms appeared, in which there is a division of function among cells—some specializing in reproduction, others becoming leaves, trunks, and roots in plants or different organs and tissues such as muscle, nerve, and bone in animals. Social organization of individuals in a population is another way of achieving functional division, which may be quite fixed, as in ants and bees, or more flexible, as in cattle herds or primate groups. Because of the gradualness of evolution, immediate descendants differ little, and then mostly quantitatively, from their ancestors. But gradual evolution may amount to large differences over time. The forelimbs of mammals are normally adapted for walking, but they are adapted for shoveling earth in moles and other mammals that live mostly underground, for climbing and grasping in arboreal monkeys and apes, for swimming in dolphins and whales, and for flying in bats. The forelimbs of reptiles became wings in their bird descendants. Feathers appear to have served first for regulating temperature but eventually were co-opted for flying and became incorporated into wings. Eyes, which serve as another example, also evolved gradually and achieved very different configurations, all serving the function of seeing. Eyes have evolved independently at least 40 times. Because sunlight is a pervasive feature of Earth's environment, it is not surprising that organs have evolved that take advantage of it. The simplest “organ” of vision occurs in some single-celled organisms that have enzymes or spots sensitive to light (see eyespot), which helps them move toward the surface of their pond, where they feed on the algae growing there by photosynthesis. Some multicellular animals exhibit light-sensitive spots on their epidermis. Further steps—deposition of pigment around the spot, configuration of cells into a cuplike shape, thickening of the epidermis leading to the development of a lens, development of muscles to move the eyes and nerves to transmit optical signals to the brain—all led to the highly developed eyes of vertebrates (see eye, human) and cephalopods (octopuses and squids) and to the compound eyes of insects. While the evolution of forelimbs—for walking—into the wings of birds or the arms and hands of primates may seem more like changes of function, the evolution of eyes exemplifies gradual advancement of the same function—seeing. In all cases, however, the process is impelled by natural selection's favouring individuals exhibiting functional advantages over others of the same species. Examples of functional shifts are many and diverse. Some transitions at first may seem unlikely because of the difficulty in identifying which possible functions may have been served during the intermediate stages. These cases are eventually resolved with further research and the discovery of intermediate fossil forms. An example of a seemingly unlikely transition is described above in the section The fossil record (evolution)—namely, the transformation of bones found in the reptilian jaw into the hammer and anvil of the mammalian ear. Evolution and development Starfish are radially symmetrical, but most animals are bilaterally symmetrical—the parts of the left and right halves of their bodies tend to correspond in size, shape, and position (see symmetry). Some bilateral animals, such as millipedes and shrimps, are segmented (metameric); others, such as frogs and humans, have a front-to-back (head-to-foot) body plan, with head, thorax, abdomen, and limbs, but they lack the repetitive, nearly identical segments of metameric animals. There are other basic body plans, such as those of sponges, clams, and jellyfish, but their total number is not large—less than 40. The fertilized egg, or zygote, is a single cell, more or less spherical, that does not exhibit polarity such as anterior and posterior ends or dorsal and ventral sides. Embryonic development (see animal development) is the process of growth and differentiation by which the single-celled egg becomes a multicellular organism. The determination of body plan from this single cell and the construction of specialized organs, such as the eye, are under the control of regulatory genes. Most notable among these are the Hox genes, which produce proteins (transcription factors) that bind with other genes and thus determine their expression—that is, when they will act. The Hox genes embody spatial and temporal information. By means of their encoded proteins, they activate or repress the expression of other genes according to the position of each cell in the developing body, determining where limbs and other body parts will grow in the embryo. Since their discovery in the early 1980s, the Hox genes have been found to play crucial roles from the first steps of development, such as establishing anterior and posterior ends in the zygote, to much later steps, such as the differentiation of nerve cells. The critical region of the Hox proteins is encoded by a sequence of about 180 consecutive nucleotides (called the homeobox). The corresponding protein region (the homeodomain), about 60 amino acids long, binds to a short stretch of DNA in the regulatory region of the target genes. Genes containing homeobox sequences are found not only in animals but also in other eukaryotes such as fungi and plants. All animals have Hox genes, which may be as few as 1, as in sponges, or as many as 38, as in humans and other mammals. Hox genes are clustered in the genome. Invertebrates have only one cluster with a variable number of genes, typically fewer than 13. The common ancestor of the chordates (which include the vertebrates) probably had only one cluster of Hox genes, which may have numbered 13. Chordates may have one or more clusters, but not all 13 genes remain in every cluster. The marine animal amphioxus, a primitive chordate, has a single array of 10 Hox genes. Humans, mice, and other mammals have 38 Hox genes arranged in four clusters, three with 9 genes each and one with 11 genes. The set of genes varies from cluster to cluster, so that out of the 13 in the original cluster, genes designated 1, 2, 3, and 7 may be missing in one set, whereas 10, 11, 12, and 13 may be missing in a different set. The four clusters of Hox genes found in mammals originated by duplication of the whole original cluster and retain considerable similarity between clusters. The 13 genes in the original cluster also themselves originated by repeated duplication, starting from a single Hox gene as found in the sponges. These first duplications happened very early in animal evolution, in the Precambrian (Precambrian time). The genes within a cluster retain detectable similarity, but they differ more from one another than they differ from the corresponding, or homologous, gene in any of the other sets. There is a puzzling correspondence between the position of the Hox genes in a cluster along the chromosome and the patterning of the body—genes located upstream (anteriorly in the direction in which genes are transcribed) in the cluster are expressed earlier and more anteriorly in the body, while those located downstream (posteriorly in the direction of transcription) are expressed later in development and predominantly affect the posterior body parts. Researchers demonstrated the evolutionary conservation of the Hox genes by means of clever manipulations of genes in laboratory experiments. For example, the ey gene that determines the formation of the compound eye in Drosophila vinegar flies (vinegar fly) was activated in the developing embryo in various parts of the body, yielding experimental flies with anatomically normal eyes on the legs, wings, and other structures. The evolutionary conservation of the Hox genes may be the explanation for the puzzling observation that most of the diversity of body plans within major groups of animals arose early in the evolution of the group. The multicellular animals (metazoans) first found as fossils in the Cambrian (Cambrian Period) already demonstrate all the major body plans found during the ensuing 540 million years, as well as four to seven additional body plans that became extinct and seem bizarre to observers today. Similarly, most of the classes found within a phylum appear early in the evolution of the phylum. For example, all living classes of arthropods are already found in the Cambrian, with body plans essentially unchanged thereafter; in addition, the Cambrian contains a few strange kinds of arthropods that later became extinct. Reconstruction of evolutionary history DNA and protein as informational macromolecules The advances of molecular biology have made possible the comparative study of proteins and the nucleic acids, DNA and RNA. DNA is the repository of hereditary (evolutionary and developmental) information. The relationship of proteins to DNA is so immediate that they closely reflect the hereditary information. This reflection is not perfect, because the genetic code is redundant, and, consequently, some differences in the DNA do not yield differences in the proteins. Moreover, this reflection is not complete, because a large fraction of DNA (about 90 percent in many organisms) does not code for proteins. Nevertheless, proteins are so closely related to the information contained in DNA that they, as well as nucleic acids, are called informational macromolecules. Nucleic acids and proteins are linear molecules made up of sequences of units— nucleotides in the case of nucleic acids, amino acids in the case of proteins—which retain considerable amounts of evolutionary information. Comparing two macromolecules (macromolecule) establishes the number of their units that are different. Because evolution usually occurs by changing one unit at a time, the number of differences is an indication of the recency of common ancestry. Changes in evolutionary rates may create difficulties in interpretation, but macromolecular studies have three notable advantages over comparative anatomy and the other classical disciplines. One is that the information is more readily quantifiable. The number of units that are different is readily established when the sequence of units is known for a given macromolecule in different organisms. The second advantage is that comparisons can be made even between very different sorts of organisms. There is very little that comparative anatomy can say when organisms as diverse as yeasts, pine trees, and human beings are compared, but there are homologous macromolecules that can be compared in all three. The third advantage is multiplicity. Each organism possesses thousands of genes and proteins, which all reflect the same evolutionary history. If the investigation of one particular gene or protein does not resolve the evolutionary relationship of a set of species, additional genes and proteins can be investigated until the matter has been settled. Informational macromolecules provide information not only about the branching of lineages from common ancestors (cladogenesis) but also about the amount of genetic change that has occurred in any given lineage (anagenesis). It might seem at first that quantifying anagenesis for proteins and nucleic acids would be impossible, because it would require comparison of molecules from organisms that lived in the past with those from living organisms. Organisms of the past are sometimes preserved as fossils, but their DNA and proteins have largely disintegrated. Nevertheless, comparisons between living species provide information about anagenesis. The following is an example of such comparison: Two living species, C and D, have a common ancestor, the extinct species B (see the left side of the figure-->). If C and D were found to differ by four amino acid substitutions in a single protein, then it could tentatively be assumed that two substitutions (four total changes divided by two species) had taken place in the evolutionary lineage of each species. This assumption, however, could be invalidated by the discovery of a third living species, E, that is related to C, D, and their ancestor, B, through an earlier ancestor, A. The number of amino acid differences between the protein molecules of the three living species may be as follows: The left side of the figure proposes a phylogeny of the three living species, making it possible to estimate the number of amino acid substitutions that have occurred in each lineage. Let x denote the number of differences between B and C, y denote the differences between B and D, and z denote the differences between A and B as well as A and E. The following three equations can be produced: Solving the equations yields x = 3, y = 1, and z = 8. As a concrete example, consider the protein cytochrome c, involved in cell respiration. The sequence of amino acids in this protein is known for many organisms, from bacteria and yeasts to insects and humans; in animals cytochrome c consists of 104 amino acids. When the amino acid sequences of humans and rhesus monkeys are compared, they are found to be different at position 66 (isoleucine in humans, threonine in rhesus monkeys) but, identical at the other 103 positions. When humans are compared with horses, 12 amino acid differences are found, but, when horses are compared with rhesus monkeys, there are only 11 amino acid differences. Even without knowing anything else about the evolutionary history of mammals, one would conclude that the lineages of humans and rhesus monkeys diverged from each other much more recently than they diverged from the horse lineage. Moreover, it can be concluded that the amino acid difference between humans and rhesus monkeys must have occurred in the human lineage after its separation from the rhesus monkey lineage (see the right side of the figure-->). Evolutionary trees Evolutionary trees are models that seek to reconstruct the evolutionary history of taxa—i.e., species or other groups of organisms, such as genera, families, or orders. The trees embrace two kinds of information related to evolutionary change, cladogenesis and anagenesis. The figure--> can be used to illustrate both kinds. The branching relationships of the trees reflect the relative relationships of ancestry, or cladogenesis. Thus, in the right side of the figure, humans and rhesus monkeys are seen to be more closely related to each other than either is to the horse. Stated another way, this tree shows that the last common ancestor to all three species lived in a more remote past than the last common ancestor to humans and monkeys. Evolutionary trees may also indicate the changes that have occurred along each lineage, or anagenesis. Thus, in the evolution of cytochrome c since the last common ancestor of humans and rhesus monkeys (again, the right side of the figure), one amino acid changed in the lineage going to humans but none in the lineage going to rhesus monkeys. Similarly, the left side of the figure shows that three amino acid changes occurred in the lineage from B to C but only one in the lineage from B to D. There exist several methods for constructing evolutionary trees. Some were developed for interpreting morphological data, others for interpreting molecular data; some can be used with either kind of data. The main methods currently in use are called distance, parsimony, and maximum likelihood. Distance methods Minimum number of nucleotide differences in genes coding for cytochrome c in 20 different organismsA “distance” is the number of differences between two taxa. The differences are measured with respect to certain traits (i.e., morphological data) or to certain macromolecules (primarily the sequence of amino acids in proteins or the sequence of nucleotides in DNA or RNA). The two trees illustrated in the figure--> were obtained by taking into account the distance, or number of amino acid differences, between three organisms with respect to a particular protein. The amino acid sequence of a protein contains more information than is reflected in the number of amino acid differences. This is because in some cases the replacement of one amino acid by another requires no more than one nucleotide substitution in the DNA that codes for the protein, whereas in other cases it requires at least two nucleotide changes. The table (Minimum number of nucleotide differences in genes coding for cytochrome c in 20 different organisms) shows the minimum number of nucleotide differences in the genes of 20 separate species that are necessary to account for the amino acid differences in their cytochrome c. An evolutionary tree based on the data in the table, showing the minimum numbers of nucleotide changes in each branch, is illustrated in the complementary figure-->. The relationships between species as shown in the figure correspond fairly well to the relationships determined from other sources, such as the fossil record. According to the figure, chickens are less closely related to ducks and pigeons than to penguins, and humans and monkeys diverged from the other mammals before the marsupial kangaroo separated from the nonprimate placentals. Although these examples are known to be erroneous relationships, the power of the method is apparent in that a single protein yields a fairly accurate reconstruction of the evolutionary history of 20 organisms that started to diverge more than one billion years ago. Morphological data also can be used for constructing distance trees. The first step is to obtain a distance matrix, such as that making up the nucleotide differences table, but one based on a set of morphological comparisons between species or other taxa. For example, in some insects one can measure body length, wing length, wing width, number and length of wing veins, or another trait. The most common procedure to transform a distance matrix into a phylogeny is called cluster analysis. The distance matrix is scanned for the smallest distance element, and the two taxa involved (say, A and B) are joined at an internal node, or branching point. The matrix is scanned again for the next smallest distance, and the two new taxa (say, C and D) are clustered. The procedure is continued until all taxa have been joined. When a distance involves a taxon that is already part of a previous cluster (say, E and A), the average distance is obtained between the new taxon and the preexisting cluster (say, the average distance between E to A and E to B). This simple procedure, which can also be used with molecular data, assumes that the rate of evolution is uniform along all branches. Other distance methods (including the one used to construct the tree in the figure--> of the 20-organism phylogeny) relax the condition of uniform rate and allow for unequal rates of evolution along the branches. One of the most extensively used methods of this kind is called neighbour-joining. The method starts, as before, by identifying the smallest distance in the matrix and linking the two taxa involved. The next step is to remove these two taxa and calculate a new matrix in which their distances to other taxa are replaced by the distance between the node linking the two taxa and all other taxa. The smallest distance in this new matrix is used for making the next connection, which will be between two other taxa or between the previous node and a new taxon. The procedure is repeated until all taxa have been connected with one another by intervening nodes. Maximum parsimony methods Maximum parsimony methods seek to reconstruct the tree that requires the fewest (i.e., most parsimonious) number of changes summed along all branches. This is a reasonable assumption, because it usually will be the most likely. But evolution may not necessarily have occurred following a minimum path, because the same change instead may have occurred independently along different branches, and some changes may have involved intermediate steps. Consider three species—C, D, and E. If C and D differ by two amino acids in a certain protein and either one differs by three amino acids from E, parsimony will lead to a tree with the structure shown in the left side of the figure--> illustrating the two simple phylogenies. It may be the case, however, that in a certain position at which C and D both have amino acid g while E has h, the ancestral amino acid was g. Amino acid g did not change in the lineage going to C but changed to h in a lineage going to the ancestor of D and E and then changed again, back to g, in the lineage going to D. The correct phylogeny would lead then from the common ancestor of all three species to C in one branch (in which no amino acid changes occurred), and to the last common ancestor of D and E in the other branch (in which g changed to h) with one additional change (from h to g) occurring in the lineage from this ancestor to E. Not all evolutionary changes, even those that involve a single step, may be equally probable. For example, among the four nucleotide bases in DNA, cytosine (C) and thymine (T) are members of a family of related molecules called pyrimidines; likewise, adenine (A) and guanine (G) belong to a family of molecules called purines. A change within a DNA sequence from one pyrimidine to another (C ⇌ T) or from one purine to another (A ⇌ G), called a transition, is more likely to occur than a change from a purine to a pyrimidine or the converse (G or A ⇌ C or T), called a transversion. Parsimony methods take into account different probabilities of occurrence if they are known. Maximum parsimony methods are related to cladistics, a very formalistic theory of taxonomic classification, extensively used with morphological and paleontological data. The critical feature in cladistics is the identification of derived shared traits, called synapomorphic traits. A synapomorphic trait is shared by some taxa but not others because the former inherited it from a common ancestor that acquired the trait after its lineage separated from the lineages going to the other taxa. In the evolution of carnivores, for example, domestic cats, tigers, and leopards are clustered together because of their possessing retractable claws, a trait acquired after their common ancestor branched off from the lineage leading to the dogs, wolves, and coyotes. It is important to ascertain that the shared traits are homologous rather than analogous. For example, mammals and birds, but not lizards, have a four-chambered heart. Yet birds are more closely related to lizards than to mammals; the four-chambered heart evolved independently in the bird and mammal lineages, by parallel evolution. Maximum likelihood methods Maximum likelihood methods seek to identify the most likely tree, given the available data. They require that an evolutionary model be identified, which would make it possible to estimate the probability of each possible individual change. For example, as is mentioned in the preceding section, transitions are more likely than transversions among DNA nucleotides, but a particular probability must be assigned to each. All possible trees are considered. The probabilities for each individual change are multiplied for each tree. The best tree is the one with the highest probability (or maximum likelihood) among all possible trees. Maximum likelihood methods are computationally expensive when the number of taxa is large, because the number of possible trees (for each of which the probability must be calculated) grows factorially with the number of taxa. With 10 taxa, there are about 3.6 million possible trees; with 20 taxa, the number of possible trees is about 2 followed by 18 zeros (2 × 1018). Even with powerful computers, maximum likelihood methods can be prohibitive if the number of taxa is large. Heuristic methods exist in which only a subsample of all possible trees is examined and thus an exhaustive search is avoided. Evaluation of evolutionary trees The statistical degree of confidence of a tree can be estimated for distance and maximum likelihood trees. The most common method is called bootstrapping. It consists of taking samples of the data by removing at least one data point at random and then constructing a tree for the new data set. This random sampling process is repeated hundreds or thousands of times. The bootstrap value for each node is defined by the percentage of cases in which all species derived from that node appear together in the trees. Bootstrap values above 90 percent are regarded as statistically strongly reliable; those below 70 percent are considered unreliable. Molecular evolution Molecular phylogeny of genes The methods for obtaining the nucleotide sequences of DNA have enormously improved since the 1980s and have become largely automated. Many genes have been sequenced in numerous organisms, and the complete genome has been sequenced in various species ranging from humans to viruses. The use of DNA sequences has been particularly rewarding in the study of gene duplications. The genes that code for the hemoglobins in humans and other mammals provide a good example. Knowledge of the amino acid sequences of the hemoglobin chains and of myoglobin, a closely related protein, has made it possible to reconstruct the evolutionary history of the duplications that gave rise to the corresponding genes. But direct examination of the nucleotide sequences in the genes coding for these proteins has shown that the situation is more complex, and also more interesting, than it appears from the protein sequences. DNA sequence studies on human hemoglobin genes have shown that their number is greater than previously thought. Hemoglobin molecules are tetramers (molecules made of four subunits), consisting of two polypeptides (relatively short protein chains) of one kind and two of another kind. In embryonic hemoglobin E, one of the two kinds of polypeptide is designated ε; in fetal hemoglogin F, it is γ; in adult hemoglobin A, it is β; and in adult hemoglobin A2, it is δ. (Hemoglobin A makes up about 98 percent of human adult hemoglobin, and hemoglobin A2 about 2 percent). The other kind of polypeptide in embryonic hemoglobin is ζ; in both fetal and adult hemoglobin, it is α. The genes coding for the first group of polypeptides (ε, γ, β, and δ) are located on chromosome 11; the genes coding for the second group of polypeptides (ζ and α) are located on chromosome 16. There are yet additional complexities. Two γ genes exist (known as Gγ and Aγ), as do two α genes (α1 and α2). Furthermore, there are two β pseudogenes (ψβ1 and ψβ2) and two α pseudogenes (ψα1 and ψα2), as well as a ζ pseudogene. These pseudogenes are very similar in nucleotide sequence to the corresponding functional genes, but they include terminating codons and other mutations that make it impossible for them to yield functional hemoglobins. The similarity in the nucleotide sequence of the polypeptide genes, and pseudogenes, of both the α and β gene families indicates that they are all homologous—that is, that they have arisen through various duplications and subsequent evolution from a gene ancestral to all. Moreover, homology also exists between the nucleotide sequences that separate one gene from another. The evolutionary history of the genes for hemoglobin and myoglobin is summarized in the figure-->. Multiplicity and rate heterogeneity Cytochrome c consists of only 104 amino acids, encoded by 312 nucleotides. Nevertheless, this short protein stores enormous evolutionary information, which made possible the fairly good approximation, shown in the figure-->, to the evolutionary history of 20 very diverse species over a period longer than one billion years. But cytochrome c is a slowly evolving protein. Widely different species have in common a large proportion of the amino acids in their cytochrome c, which makes possible the study of genetic differences between organisms only remotely related. For the same reason, however, comparing cytochrome c molecules cannot determine evolutionary relationships between closely related species. For example, the amino acid sequence of cytochrome c in humans and chimpanzees is identical, although they diverged about 6 million years ago; between humans and rhesus monkeys, which diverged from their common ancestor 35 million to 40 million years ago, it differs by only one amino acid replacement. Proteins that evolve more rapidly than cytochrome c can be studied in order to establish phylogenetic relationships between closely related species. Some proteins evolve very fast; the fibrinopeptides—small proteins involved in the blood-clotting process—are suitable for reconstructing the phylogeny of recently evolved species, such as closely related mammals. Other proteins evolve at intermediate rates; the hemoglobins, for example, can be used for reconstructing evolutionary history over a fairly broad range of time (see figure-->). One great advantage of molecular evolution is its multiplicity, as noted above in the section DNA and protein as informational macromolecules (evolution). Within each organism are thousands of genes and proteins; these evolve at different rates, but every one of them reflects the same evolutionary events. Scientists can obtain greater and greater accuracy in reconstructing the evolutionary phylogeny of any group of organisms by increasing the number of genes investigated. The range of differences in the rates of evolution between genes opens up the opportunity of investigating different sets of genes for achieving different degrees of resolution in the tree, relying on slowly evolving ones for remote evolutionary events. Even genes that encode slowly evolving proteins can be useful for reconstructing the evolutionary relationships between closely related species, by examination of the redundant codon substitutions (nucleotide substitutions that do not change the encoded amino acids), the introns (noncoding DNA segments interspersed among the segments that code for amino acids), or other noncoding segments of the genes (such as the sequences that precede and follow the encoding portions of genes); these generally evolve much faster than the nucleotides that specify the amino acids. The molecular clock of evolution One conspicuous attribute of molecular evolution is that differences between homologous molecules can readily be quantified and expressed, as, for example, proportions of nucleotides or amino acids that have changed. Rates of evolutionary change can therefore be more precisely established with respect to DNA or proteins than with respect to phenotypic (phenotype) traits of form and function. Studies of molecular evolution rates have led to the proposition that macromolecules may serve as evolutionary clocks. It was first observed in the 1960s that the numbers of amino acid differences between homologous proteins of any two given species seemed to be nearly proportional to the time of their divergence from a common ancestor. If the rate of evolution of a protein or gene were approximately the same in the evolutionary lineages leading to different species, proteins and DNA sequences would provide a molecular clock of evolution. The sequences could then be used to reconstruct not only the sequence of branching events of a phylogeny but also the time when the various events occurred. Consider, for example, the figure--> depicting the 20-organism phylogeny. If the substitution of nucleotides in the gene coding for cytochrome c occurred at a constant rate through time, one could determine the time elapsed along any branch of the phylogeny simply by examining the number of nucleotide substitutions along that branch. One would need only to calibrate the clock by reference to an outside source, such as the fossil record, that would provide the actual geologic time elapsed in at least one specific lineage. The molecular evolutionary clock, of course, is not expected to be a metronomic clock, like a watch or other timepiece that measures time exactly, but a stochastic clock like radioactive decay. In a stochastic clock the probability of a certain amount of change is constant (for example, a given quantity of atoms of radium-226 is expected, through decay, to be reduced by half in 1,620 years), although some variation occurs in the actual amount of change. Over fairly long periods of time a stochastic clock is quite accurate. The enormous potential of the molecular evolutionary clock lies in the fact that each gene or protein is a separate clock. Each clock “ticks” at a different rate—the rate of evolution characteristic of a particular gene or protein—but each of the thousands and thousands of genes or proteins provides an independent measure of the same evolutionary events. Evolutionists have found that the amount of variation observed in the evolution of DNA and proteins is greater than is expected from a stochastic clock—in other words, the clock is erratic. The discrepancies in evolutionary rates along different lineages are not excessively large, however. So it is possible, in principle, to time phylogenetic events with as much accuracy as may be desired, but more genes or proteins (about two to four times as many) must be examined than would be required if the clock was stochastically constant. The average rates obtained for several proteins taken together become a fairly precise clock, particularly when many species are studied and the evolutionary events involve long time periods (on the order of 50 million years or longer). This conclusion is illustrated in the figure, which plots the cumulative number of nucleotide changes in seven proteins against the dates of divergence of 17 species of mammals (16 pairings) as determined from the fossil record. The overall rate of nucleotide substitution is fairly uniform. Some primate species (the pairs represented by triangular points in the figure) appear to have evolved at a slower rate than the average for the rest of the species. This anomaly occurs because the more recent the divergence of any two species, the more likely it is that the changes observed will depart from the average evolutionary rate. As the length of time increases, periods of rapid and slow evolution in any lineage are likely to cancel one another out. Evolutionists have discovered, however, that molecular time estimates tend to be systematically older than estimates based on other methods and, indeed, to be older than the actual dates. This is a consequence of the statistical properties of molecular estimates, which are asymmetrically distributed. Because of chance, the number of molecular differences between two species may be larger or smaller than expected. But overestimation errors are unbounded, whereas underestimation errors are bounded, since they cannot be smaller than zero. Consequently, a graph of a typical distribution (see normal distribution) of estimates of the age when two species diverged, gathered from a number of different genes, is skewed from the normal bell shape, with a large number of estimates of younger age clustered together at one end and a long “tail” of older-age estimates trailing away toward the other end. The average of the estimated times thus will consistently overestimate the true date. The overestimation bias becomes greater when the rate of molecular evolution is slower, the sequences used are shorter, and the time becomes increasingly remote. The neutrality theory of molecular evolution In the late 1960s it was proposed that at the molecular level most evolutionary changes are selectively “neutral,” meaning that they are due to genetic drift rather than to natural selection. Nucleotide and amino acid substitutions appear in a population by mutation. If alternative alleles (alternative DNA sequences) have identical fitness—if they are identically able to perform their function—changes in allelic frequency from generation to generation will occur only by genetic drift. Rates of allelic substitution will be stochastically constant—that is, they will occur with a constant probability for a given gene or protein. This constant rate is the mutation rate for neutral alleles. According to the neutrality theory, a large proportion of all possible mutants at any gene locus are harmful to their carriers. These mutants are eliminated by natural selection, just as standard evolutionary theory postulates. The neutrality theory also agrees that morphological, behavioral, and ecological traits evolve under the control of natural selection. What is distinctive in the theory is the claim that at each gene locus there are several favourable mutants, equivalent to one another with respect to adaptation, so that they are not subject to natural selection among themselves. Which of these mutants increases or decreases in frequency in one or another species is purely a matter of chance, the result of random genetic drift over time. Neutral alleles are those that differ so little in fitness that their frequencies change by random drift rather than by natural selection. This definition is formally stated as 4Nes \\< 1, where Ne is the effective size of the population and s is the selective coefficient that measures the difference in fitness between the alleles. Assume that k is the rate of substitution of neutral alleles per unit time in the course of evolution. The time units can be years or generations. In a random-mating population with N diploid individuals, k = 2Nux, where u is the neutral mutation rate per gamete per unit time (time measured in the same units as for k) and x is the probability of ultimate fixation of a neutral mutant. The derivation of this equation is straightforward: there are 2Nu mutants per time unit, each with a probability x of becoming fixed. In a population of N diploid individuals there are 2N genes at each locus, all of them, if they are neutral, with an identical probability, x = 1/(2N), of becoming fixed. If this value of x is substituted in the equation above (k = 2Nux), the result is k = u. In terms of the theory, then, the rate of substitution of neutral alleles is precisely the rate at which the neutral alleles arise by mutation, independently of the number of individuals in the population or of any other factors. If the neutrality theory of molecular evolution is strictly correct, it will provide a theoretical foundation for the hypothesis of the molecular evolutionary clock, since the rate of neutral mutation would be expected to remain constant through evolutionary time and in different lineages. The number of amino acid or nucleotide differences between species would, therefore, simply reflect the time elapsed since they shared the last common ancestor. Evolutionists debate whether the neutrality theory is valid. Tests of the molecular clock hypothesis indicate that the variations in the rates of molecular evolution are substantially larger than would be expected according to the neutrality theory. Other tests have revealed substantial discrepancies between the amount of genetic polymorphism found in populations of a given species and the amount predicted by the theory. But defenders of the theory argue that these discrepancies can be assimilated by modifying the theory somewhat—by assuming, for example, that alleles are not strictly neutral but their differences in selective value are quite small. Be that as it may, the neutrality theory provides a “null hypothesis,” or point of departure, for measuring molecular evolution. Additional Reading Modern treatments of the theory Modern treatments of evolutionary theory include Ernst Mayr, What Evolution Is (2001), a readable yet authoritative and comprehensive overview addressed to the general public; and G. Ledyard Stebbins, Darwin to DNA, Molecules to Humanity (1982), which extends to cover human evolution, both biological and cultural. Michael R. Rose, Darwin's Spectre: Evolutionary Biology in the Modern World (1998, reissued 2000), introduces the theory of evolution and its application to agriculture, medicine, sociology, and religion. A voluminous and authoritative but idiosyncratic treatise is Stephen Jay Gould, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory (2002). Comprehensive college-level texts are Douglas J. Futuyma, Evolutionary Biology, 3rd ed. (1998); and Monroe W. Strickberger, Evolution, 3rd ed. (2000). A more advanced text is Theodosius Dobzhansky et al., Evolution (1977). An authoritative collection of writings by multiple authors is Andrés Moya and Enrique Font (eds.), Evolution: From Molecules to Ecosystems (2004). A useful selection of texts is found in Philip Appleman (ed.), Darwin: Texts Commentary, 3rd ed. (2001), with excerpts extending from Darwin and his immediate predecessors, through scientific considerations, to social, philosophical, and religious issues, including a section demonstrating Darwin's impact on the literary mind. Classic works Early seminal works of evolutionary theory include Charles Darwin and Alfred Wallace, “On the Tendency of Species to Form Varieties, and on the Perpetuation of Varieties and Species by Natural Means of Selection,” Journal of the Proceedings of the Linnean Society, 3(9):45–62 (1858); and Charles Darwin, On the Origin of the Species by Means of Natural Selection; or, The Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (1859), also available in many modern editions, and The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, 2 vol. (1871, reprinted in 1 vol., 1981). Gregor Mendel, Experiments in Plant Hybridisation (1965; originally published in German, 1866), provides the groundwork for all subsequent studies in heredity, including R.A. Fisher, The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection, ed. by J.H. Bennett, 2nd rev. ed. (1958, reissued 1999); and J.B.S. Haldane, The Causes of Evolution (1932, reprinted with corrections, 1993). Theodosius Dobzhansky, Genetics and the Origin of Species (1937, reprinted 1982), is the classic foundation of the synthetic theory of evolution; also of interest is Julian Huxley, Evolution: The Modern Synthesis, 3rd ed. (1974). History and biography The history of evolutionary theories from Darwin to the present is traced in Ronald W. Clark, The Survival of Charles Darwin: A Biography of a Man and an Idea (1984, reissued 1986), which also presents an engaging biography of Darwin. The most authoritative historical treatise on evolutionary ideas from antiquity to the present is Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance (1982). Ernst Mayr and William B. Provine (eds.), The Evolutionary Synthesis: Perspectives on the Unification of Biology (1980, reissued 1998), contains historical articles by several of the great evolutionists who formulated the synthetic theory. Two historical treatises with philosophical perspectives are Peter J. Bowler, Evolution: The History of the Idea, rev. and expanded 3rd ed. (2003); and Michael Ruse, Monad to Man: The Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology (1996). An authoritative biography is John Bowlby, Charles Darwin: A New Life (1990, reissued 1992). A very engaging biography, with fictionalized dialogue extracted from Darwin's correspondence and other writings, is Irvine Stone, The Origin: A Biographical Novel of Charles Darwin, ed. by Jean Stone (1980, reissued 1982). Darwin's voyage of discovery is covered in Alan Moorehead, Darwin and the Beagle (1969, reissued with a new introduction, 2000). Religious and social aspects Two excellent collections of papers on the evolution-versus-religion dialogue are Robert John Russell, William R. Stoeger, and Francisco J. Ayala (eds.), Evolutionary and Molecular Biology: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action (1998), with contributions from scientists and religious scholars from diverse Christian denominations and including the 1996 statement of John Paul II on the subject; and James B. Miller (ed.), An Evolving Dialogue: Theological and Scientific Perspectives on Evolution (1998, reissued 2001), an extensive collection that includes in its final part papers by the proponents of the theory of intelligent design. Kenneth R. Miller, Finding Darwin's God: A Scientist's Search for Common Ground Between God and Evolution (1999, reissued 2002), is a thoughtful but forceful critique of evolutionary materialism as well as of creationism and intelligent design. John A. Moore, From Genesis to Genetics: The Case of Evolution and Creationism (2002), is a very readable discussion of the subject. More advanced discussions are Eugenie C. Scott, Evolution vs. Creationism: An Introduction (2004); Robert T. Pennock, Tower of Babel: The Evidence Against the New Creationism (1999); and Massimo Pigliucci, Denying Evolution: Creationism, Scientism, and the Nature of Science (2002). The classic presentation of the argument from intelligent design is William Paley, Natural Theology (1802); a modern presentation is Michael J. Behe, Darwin's Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution (1996, reissued 2003). Natural selection, adaptation, and speciation Investigations of the modes of natural selection and how they account for adaptation are Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, new ed. (2000); Michael R. Rose and George V. Lauder (eds.), Adaptation (1996); and Timothy A. Mousseau, Barry Sinervo, and John A. Endler (eds.), Adaptive Genetic Variation in the Wild (2000). The adaptive evolution of finches in the Galapagos is the subject of Peter R. Grant, Ecology and Evolution of Darwin's Finches (1986, reissued 1999); this topic is presented in a popular version by Jonathan Weiner, The Beak of the Finch: A Story of Evolution in Our Time (1994). Francisco J. Ayala, Population and Evolutionary Genetics: A Primer (1982), provides an introduction to the genetics of the evolutionary process. More advanced and mathematically demanding works are Philip W. Hedrick, Genetics of Populations, 2nd ed. (2000); and Daniel L. Hartl and Andrew G. Clark, Principles of Population Genetics, 3rd ed. (1997). The origin of species is the subject of Michael J.D. White, Modes of Speciation (1978); and of the more comprehensive Ernst Mayr, Animal Species and Evolution (1963; also published as Population, Species, and Evolution, 1970), which is a classic work. G. Ledyard Stebbins, Flowering Plants: Evolution Above the Species Level (1974), discusses plant speciation and evolution. A useful textbook is Jerry A. Coyne and H. Allen Orr, Speciation (2004). Paleontology and evolution A good introduction to the fossil record is a collection of articles from Scientific American, edited by Léo F. Laporte, The Fossil Record and Evolution (1982). George Gaylord Simpson, The Meaning of Evolution: A Study of the History of Life and of Its Significance for Man, 2nd rev. ed. (1967, reissued 1971), is written for the general reader yet is an authoritative work dealing particularly with paleontological principles and the evolutionary process through time; somewhat more technical is his Major Features of Evolution, 3rd ed. (1961, reissued 1969). An authoritative treatise on paleontological principles is Stephen Jay Gould, Ontogeny and Phylogeny (1977). A readable review of the history of life is Steven M. Stanley, Earth and Life Through Time, 2nd ed. (1989, reissued 1993). More advanced treatises are James W. Valentine (ed.), Phanerozoic Diversity Patterns: Profiles in Macroevolution (1985); and Geerat J. Vermeij, Evolution and Escalation: An Ecological History of Life (1987). Molecular evolution A good introduction to molecular evolution is Don Graur and Wen-Hsiung Li, Fundamentals of Molecular Evolution, 2nd ed. (1999). More-advanced treatments are Wen-Hsiung Li, Molecular Evolution (1997); John C. Avise, Molecular Markers, Natural History, and Evolution, 2nd ed. (2004); and David M. Hillis, Craig Moritz, and Barbara K. Mable (eds.), Molecular Systematics, 2nd ed. (1996). The neutrality theory is presented in full by its main theorizer in Motoo Kimura, The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution (1983); and the theory that evolutionary changes happen not gradually but abruptly is advanced by one of its originators in Niles Eldredge, Time Frames: The Rethinking of Darwinian Evolution and the Theory of Punctuated Equilibria (1985; reissued as Time Frames: The Theory of Punctuated Equilibria, 1989). |
随便看 |
|
百科全书收录100133条中英文百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容开放、自由的电子版百科全书。